30.09.2013 Views

Symposium - AIC

Symposium - AIC

Symposium - AIC

SHOW MORE
SHOW LESS

You also want an ePaper? Increase the reach of your titles

YUMPU automatically turns print PDFs into web optimized ePapers that Google loves.

Olga Alieva<br />

characteristic of the sophistic writings. Lysias mentions moral perfection among the reasons to yield<br />

to the non-lover. 10<br />

If we give a closer look to the extant specimens of sophistic oratory, we’ll note that though Eros and<br />

beauty (both physical and literary) do occupy an exceptional place here, 11 nothing is said concerning<br />

their “moral” influence whereas both in the <strong>Symposium</strong> and in the Phaedrus it is this aspect that<br />

comes to the fore. In Isocrates we even find the motif of voluntary slavery for the sake of beauty, 12 but<br />

for him, this slavery requires no justification like moral perfection. Even for Gorgias it would be farfetched<br />

to claim that Helen has become “better” due to her passion for Paris: as playful as an<br />

argument might be, it should nonetheless remain within the domain of εἰκός.<br />

But the problem is deeper than that: technical παιδεία of the sophists is absolutely unconcerned with<br />

erotic disposition of the person being converted. His χάρις is of no interest to the teacher. 13 On the<br />

contrary, in the earliest testimonies on Socrates his paideia is so to say sexually connoted. Thus, in<br />

Aristophanes’ Clouds, Socrates is presented on the one hand as the cheerleader of the sophistic<br />

movement, 14 and on the other hand as a sexually licentious person. 15 Far from being historically<br />

reliable, this image testifies to the effect that Socratic education was understood “in terms of eros” as<br />

late as in 423 BC. 16<br />

Polycrates might have developped some of the motifs present in Aristophanes. After Polycrates’<br />

accusation, 17 there were attempts to reconsider the Socratic eros (“corruption”) in a more positive<br />

way. It is at this point when eros and moral protreptic become associated: it would be pointless to look<br />

for something similar in non-Socratic literature. That is why I am inclined to think that Pausanias’<br />

speech is not a specimen of some generalized “sophistic” reasoning, 18 but a response to one particular<br />

sophist, 19 Antisthenes.<br />

10 Phaedr. 233a4−5: “And then, too, it will be better for your character (βελτίονί σοι προσήκει γενέσθαι) to yield to me than<br />

to a lover” (hereinafter Fowler’s transl.). Cfr. note 545.<br />

11 See, e.g., Gorg. Helen. 11. 110−111: “If, (being) a god, (love has) the divine power of the gods, how could a lesser being<br />

reject and refuse it?” (transl. by G. Kennedy in Sprague, op. cit., 30 ff). According to Gorias, the power of eros is that of<br />

“impression”: “the sight engraves upon the mind images of things which have been seen” (εἰκόνας τῶν ὁρωµένων<br />

πραγµάτων ἡ ὄψις ἐνέγραψεν ἐν τῶι φρονήµατι). Εros is therefore compulsory (cfr. 11. 125: ἔρωτος ἀνάγκαις), just like<br />

λόγος is, — one can hardly resist it; still, nothing is said concerning their “moral” influence. Isocrates also dealt extensively<br />

with the exceptional power (54.5: δύναµιν; 55. 6: ῥώµην) of beauty in his Helen, where he claims that “beauty is of all things<br />

the most venerated, the most precious, and the most divine.”<br />

12 Isocr. Helen. 57: “we submit more willingly to be the slaves of such than to rule all others, and we are more grateful to<br />

them when they impose many tasks upon us than to those who demand nothing at all” (ἥδιον δουλεύοµεν τοῖς τοιούτοις ἢ<br />

τῶν ἄλλων ἄρχοµεν…) Transl. by G. Norlin.<br />

13 Gaiser tries to overcome this difficulty by pointing to Ps.-Demosthenes’ Erotikos: “Der ἐραστής empfiehlt seinem<br />

Liebling eine sophistische Ausbildung, der er selbst nicht zu leisten vermag” (op. cit., 69). “Eine solche äußerliche<br />

Verquickung der sophistisch-paideutischen und der erotisch erotisch-paideutischen Werbung in der Form des protreptischen<br />

Logos Erotikos ist nun aber auch für die Zeit der Sophisten vor dem Aufkommen der sokratischen Literatur zu vermuten”,<br />

he argues. However, this is not convincing for the writing in question is a later one (presumably, 350 th BC) and is most likely<br />

influenced by the Socratic literature. On Ps.-Demosthenes, see: Blass, F., Die Attische Beredsamkeit III. 1: Demosthenes,<br />

Leipzig, 1893, 406 ff.; Wendland, P., Anaximenes von Lampsakos: Studien zur ältesten Geschichte der Rhetorik, Berlin,<br />

1905, 71 ff.<br />

14 See: Shichalin, Y., “Was the image of Socrates–Pythagorean Plato’s invention?”, in the Socrates and the Socratic<br />

Dialogue, ed. Ch. Moore et al. (in print). Shichalin observes that Aristophanes’ Socrates worshipes the Clouds as the gods of<br />

the sophists’ (Nub. 331: Σω. οὐ γὰρ µὰ Δί' οἶσθ' ὁτιὴ πλείστους αὗται βόσκουσι σοφιστάς), whereas the Clouds consider<br />

Socrates to be inferior only to Prodicus (Nub. 360-361: οὐ γὰρ ἂν ἄλλῳ γ' ὑπακούσαιµεν τῶν νῦν µετεωροσοφιστῶν // πλὴν<br />

ἢ Προδίκῳ); the graduate of Socrates’ school is supposed to become a sophist (Nub. 1111: ἀµέλει, κοµιεῖ τοῦτον σοφιστὴν<br />

δεξιόν). Note that Aristophanes’ Socrates is engaged in typically sophistic activity: linguistic contrivances, making the just<br />

logos unjust etc.<br />

15 The Just Logos claims that Socrates’ παιδεία will fill the young boy “with the lewdness of Antimachus” (1022:<br />

καταπυγοσύνης; cfr. 909: καταπύγων εἶ κἀναίσχυντος) and eventually will make him εὐρύπρωκτος (1085). Dover maintains<br />

that these terms were associated with passive homosexualism. See: Dover, K.J., Greek Homosexuality, Cambridge, Mass.,<br />

1989, 141.<br />

16 I don’t think that what we find in Aristophanes is more than an obsentity, a rude joke which is not supposed to be taken<br />

literally (neither is contemporary abusive language!). Nevertheless, it doesn’t enable to maintain that “no one before<br />

Aeschines proposed to understand the protreptic and educational influence of Socrates in terms of eros” (Kahn, Ch.,<br />

“Aeschines on Socratic Eros”, 93). A useful survey of Aristophanes’ attitude to eros (as connected with sophistry) may be<br />

found in: Rosen, S., Plato’s <strong>Symposium</strong>, New Haven, 1968, 120 ff.<br />

17 In Polycrates, Socrates’ corrupting influence was illustrated with the example of Alcibiades. Isocrates witnesses in his<br />

Busiris that this was a novelty, for before Polycrates no one heard of Alcibiades as a student of Socrates. Isocr. Bus. 5.9−13.<br />

Livingstone, N., A Commentary on Isocrates’ Busiris, Leiden; Boston, 2001, 38.<br />

18 Rosen notes that Pausanias’ “sexual inversion” is “assisted by the teaching of the Sophists” (op.cit., 86). It is agreed that<br />

Pausanias was a pupil of Prodicus; see: Nails, D., The People of Plato: a Prosopography of Plato and Other Socratics,<br />

Indianapolis, 2002, 222; cfr. Hunter, R., Plato’s <strong>Symposium</strong>, Oxford, 2004, 43.<br />

19 We know that Antisthenes edorsed some key sophistic attitudes, for instance, τὴν ἀρετὴν διδακτὴν εἶναι (SSR V A 99 =<br />

DL VI 105, see note 34 below), and studied with Gorgias. He is one of the “sophists” Isocrates addresses in his In sophistas.<br />

154

Hooray! Your file is uploaded and ready to be published.

Saved successfully!

Ooh no, something went wrong!