30.09.2013 Views

Symposium - AIC

Symposium - AIC

Symposium - AIC

SHOW MORE
SHOW LESS

You also want an ePaper? Increase the reach of your titles

YUMPU automatically turns print PDFs into web optimized ePapers that Google loves.

Claudia Luchetti<br />

the first, is that in the following myth about the genealogy of Love it is possible to recognize, as it has<br />

already been noticed, under the guise of Poros and Penia, the ἕν and ἀόριστος δυάς of the oral<br />

teaching. The second, much more important from my point of view, is that maybe in the only true<br />

definition of the Good contained in the platonic dialogues, precisely in the Phaedo (99c1-6), the<br />

ἀγαθόν is the authentic immortal power that truly keeps and connects (everything) together… ὡς<br />

ἀληθῶς τὸ ἀγαθὸν καὶ δέον συνδεῖν καὶ συνέχειν.<br />

Following this suggestion, Eros would be an icon of the Good, by virtue of its being fruit of<br />

the mixture between the two Principles, both dominated from a Unique ἀρχή which, being identical<br />

with the mixture, the product of this fusion, is immanent to them, while being the cause of the Union,<br />

constituting therefore their ontological foundation, transcends them both.<br />

Not only Eros, also the φιλόσοφος par excellence is a faithful image of the Good: Socrates.<br />

The only man that can be regarded as demonic (see 203a4-5, 219b7-c2), the only true expert in<br />

matters of Love (see 177d6-8, 198c5 ff.), Socrates is, like the Instant in which the Beauty-Good<br />

irrupts in the Soul (ἐξαίφνης, 210e4, 213c1), being in the middle between wisdom and ignorance (see<br />

201e10-202a10), an ἄτοπος φύσις µεταξύ (see Symp. 175a10-b3, 221d2, and Parm. 156d1-e3). But<br />

his ἀτόπια is the same θαυµασιότης of Beauty itself (see 210e4-5 e 213e2, 215b8, 216c7, 219c1,<br />

220a4, a7, 221c3, c6). Precisely this wonder discloses the deepest feature of Socrates’ personality, his<br />

being ἄφθονος (see Symp. 210d6 and, for example, Euthyphr. 3b5-d9, Phaed. 61d9-e4), that is,<br />

ἀγαθός (see Tim. 29e1-3).<br />

Obviously, the ultimate reason for the supremacy of Diotima’s agathological perspective on<br />

Aristophanes’ henology, takes root in the source of that primordial antinomy which, by means of an<br />

analogy, tells the ἀγαθόν as ἰδέα and οὐσία, being the highest giver of Form, and as “beyond” Form,<br />

at once (ἐπέκεινα τῆς οὐσίας, 509b9-10), so, literally, as οὐκ ἰδέα and οὐκ οὐσία (509b8-9).<br />

The λόγος of Diotima shows us that it is not necessary to follow only one among these two<br />

ways, excluding the other, for it is exactly in the Union with that what is pre-eminently Idea, Beauty<br />

itself (210e6-211b5), that the whole generative πρεσβεία and δύναµις of the Good become manifest.<br />

Only from a συνουσία (Symp. 211d8, 212a2) with this kind of ‘Unity’, better to say, of<br />

unifying cause, or Non Duality, and neither with a primary but undifferentiated unity, nor with a<br />

derived or second degree unity (see Aristophanes, respectively 191c7, 192c5, c6), the procreation in<br />

the Beauty (τόκος ἐν καλῷ, 206b7-8) becomes possible: as in the Republic from the erotic µείξις of<br />

the philosopher with the οὐσία gush out νοῦς, ἀλήθεια and ἐπιστήµη (book VI 490a 8-b8), so in the<br />

<strong>Symposium</strong>, from the coexistence with Beauty the Soul generates the ‘remaining’ offspring (Resp. VI<br />

507a1-5) of ἀγαθόν, true ἀρετή (212a2-7).<br />

The “Primordial Nature” and Aristophanes’ One reviewed in an agathological perspective.<br />

To conclude, the conception of a Good including in itself dialectically the One, allows us to take a<br />

retrospective look at Aristophanes’ speech, in order to focus in it on some further platonic facets of<br />

the relationship between ἀγαθόν, ψυχή and ἕν.<br />

Naturally, one could doubt about the correctness of an attempt aimed at finding in the<br />

description of the divided humans strict correspondences with the two fundamental methods of<br />

platonic Dialectics.<br />

It is a state of fact though, that the dividing by two completed by Zeus, and underlined with a<br />

certain insistence (διατεµῶ δίχα, Symp. 190d1, τεµῶ δίχα, d5, ἔτεµε τοὺς ἀνθρώπους δίχα, d7, ἡ<br />

φύσις δίχα ἐτµήθη, 191a5-6), occurs as terminus technicus and is perfectly interchangeable with the<br />

well known δίχα διαιρεῖν of the dialogues commonly regarded as dialectical (see Soph. 221e2,<br />

265a11, 265e8, Polit. from 261b4 to 302c8, Phil. 49a9, and Leg. V 745c5, d2), but it is used also at<br />

the beginning of the famous Simile with the Line in Republic VI 509d6.<br />

As far as the reduction to unity is concerned, even if at this point of the account, Aristophanes<br />

seems to understand the desire of interrelation and conjunction of the two halves in a mainly sexual<br />

sense, the choice falls on formulations like συµπλεκόµενοι in 191a7, συνεπλέκετο, 191b3, ἐν τῇ<br />

συµπλοκῇ, 191c4, and συµπεπλεγµένοι, 191e8-192a1, typical for the συµπλοκὴ τῶν εἰδῶν (see Soph.<br />

259e6, 240c1, 262c6, Theaet. 202b5, and Polit. 278b2 till 309e10, and particularly the meaningful<br />

connection between συµπλέκειν and the agathological συνδεῖν in 309a8 ff.). The συναγωγή instead,<br />

considered as erotic instrument put at our disposal from the conjunct action of Zeus and Apollo to<br />

cure the human nature, is explicitly mentioned also in 191d3 (συναγωγεύς).<br />

Furthermore, it is very interesting to observe that through the process of individualization or<br />

individuation carried out by Apollo on each half, to heal the wounds produced by the scission (190e2-<br />

191a5), it is possible to restore the conditions of that inner order (see κοσµιώτερος, 190e4), necessary<br />

299

Hooray! Your file is uploaded and ready to be published.

Saved successfully!

Ooh no, something went wrong!