30.09.2013 Views

Symposium - AIC

Symposium - AIC

Symposium - AIC

SHOW MORE
SHOW LESS

You also want an ePaper? Increase the reach of your titles

YUMPU automatically turns print PDFs into web optimized ePapers that Google loves.

Why Agathon’s Beauty Matters<br />

Francisco J. Gonzalez<br />

When I kiss Agathon my soul is on my lips,<br />

whither it comes, poor thing, hoping to cross over 1<br />

There is a tendency to treat Agathon’s as the most superficial and philosophically vacuous speech in<br />

the dialogue. 2 This impression is of course encouraged by Socrates who characterizes the speech as a<br />

piece of Gorgianic rhetoric concerned only with impressing through its choice of words and phrases<br />

and not at all with telling the truth about its subject. In other words, Socrates suggests that the speech<br />

is an attractive or beautiful one (καλὸν οὕτω καὶ παντοδαπὸν λόγον ῥηθέντα198b3), but not a good<br />

one. Indeed the speech makes love itself something merely attractive but not good, like the author in<br />

whose image it is conceived: despite his name, Agathon is more pretty boy than good.<br />

But careful consideration of Agathon’s speech and its place in the dialogue shows that this<br />

assessment cannot stand. Considering first its place in the dialogue, Agathon’s speech immediately<br />

precedes Socrates’ and is thus given a prominent, central place in the dialogue. If we see the series of<br />

speeches as an ascent of some sort, Agathon’s is near the top. One could of course in response reject<br />

the view that the speeches represent an ascent, as many scholars have precisely in order to avoid<br />

giving Agathon’s speech too much honor 3 But we do not need to assume such an ascent in order to<br />

see in the position of Agathon’s speech a sign of its importance. The reason is that the <strong>Symposium</strong><br />

explicitly justifies this position by making it clear that Socrates’ contest is with Agathon more than<br />

with any other participant. Right near the start we have Socrates’ ironic comparison of his wisdom<br />

with that of Agathon’s and then Agathon’s suggestion that Dionysus will soon decide their claims to<br />

wisdom (175e7-9). We are reminded of this towards the dialogue’s end when Alcibiades in the guise<br />

of Dionysus first crowns Agathon and then, upon seeing Socrates, crowns him as well (note that both<br />

are crowned). 4 Furthermore, if Socrates claims expertise in love (177d7-8), Eryximachus suggests that<br />

Socrates and Agathon are the two experts in love among the party (193e4-5). Now why would Plato<br />

set up this contest and this rivalry if he thought that Agathon was a mere airhead with nothing but<br />

1 “τὴν ψυχὴν ᾽Αγάθωνα φιλῶν ἐπὶ χείλεσιν ἔσχον. ἦλθε γὰρ ἡ τλήµων ὡς διαβησοµένη” This verse is attributed to Plato by<br />

Diogenes Laertius (3, 23, 32), among others. See final note of paper.<br />

2 Though acknowledging that “some valuable points are made”, Waterfield characterizes Agathon’s speech as “little more<br />

than a tour de force” (Plato: <strong>Symposium</strong> [Oxford University Press, 2009], xxiv) and concludes: “Underneath the pretty<br />

exterior lies a conventional encomium and a conventional view of Love, which reflects the god’s portraits we can find in<br />

paintings and in literature. It is therefore a perfect speech for Agathon the artist” (xxv). Note this damning last sentence on<br />

the ‘artist’. Such a judgment can be found already in Bury who judges the content of the speech purely conventional and<br />

suggests that nothing better describes it than the Pauline phrase: “Though he speaks with the tongues of men and of angels, ,<br />

he is become as sounding brass or a tinkling cymbal.” (R. G. Bury, The <strong>Symposium</strong> of Plato [Cambridge: W. Heffer and<br />

Sons, 1909]). Though one could multiply the examples of such a judgment ad nauseam, let us just add Luc Brisson’s<br />

description of the speech as “empty but magnificently constructed” (“Agathon, Pausanias, and Diotima in Plato’s<br />

<strong>Symposium</strong>; Paiderastia and Philosophia,” in Plato’s <strong>Symposium</strong>: Issues in Interpretation and Reception, eds. Lesher, Nails,<br />

Sheffield [Harvard University Press, 2006], 245).<br />

3 Kenneth Dorter has argued that the speeches cannot form an ascent, but must instead be interpreted dialectically, on the<br />

basis of his unquestioned assumption that the speech of Agathon “even allowing for its humorous intent, can hardly be<br />

placed above (or even alongside of) the inspired myth of his predecessor Aristophanes” (“A Dual Dialectic in the<br />

<strong>Symposium</strong>,” Philosophy and Rhetoric 25, no. 3 [1992]: 253-254). Bury already made the same point in arguing that the<br />

thesis of an ascending order is made untenable by “the obvious fact that Agathon’s speech is in no real sense the best or most<br />

important of the series; rather, from the point of view of Socrates, it is the worst.” One exception to this tendency is David<br />

Sedley, “The Speech of Agathon in Plato’s <strong>Symposium</strong>,” in The Virtuous Life in Greek Ethics, eds. Stella Haffmans &<br />

Burkhard Reis (Cambridge University Press, 2006), pp. 47-69. Defending what he calls the ‘crescendo’ interpretation of the<br />

speeches, Sedley interprets Agathon’s speech as being the one closest to Socrates’ own, even calling it ‘sub-Socratic’. As<br />

will be noted below, some of the observations Sedley makes in support of this reading coincide with the points made here,<br />

though some exception will be taken to his overall account of Agathon’s role in the dialogue and of his relation to Socrates.<br />

4 A point rightly emphasized by Steven Robinson, “The Contest of Wisdom between Socrates and Agathon in Plato’s<br />

<strong>Symposium</strong>,” Ancient Philosophy 24 (2004): 93. Robinson interprets this double-crowning as an indication of two sides of<br />

the worship of Dionysos: the public polis-cult, represented by Agathon with his dramatic victory at a Dionysian festival, and<br />

the private mystery-cult, represented by Socrates through his account of eros in the voice of Diotima and in the language of<br />

the mystery religions: see especially p. 87. Agathon and Socrates on this interpretation are both legitimated, the first as<br />

representing discourse that “is exoteric and public, and extends to all citizens, who all partake of it” and the second as<br />

representing discourse that “is esoteric and private, and extends only to those few citizens who are capable of meeting its<br />

very high demands, and who also participate in the public discourse” (98). But this interpretation, apart from its Straussian<br />

tendency of reducing all issues (in this case eros!) to the political one of exoteric versus esoteric discourse, appears to<br />

eliminate any real contest between Agathon and Socrates: if each has his own domain, what is the contest for?

Hooray! Your file is uploaded and ready to be published.

Saved successfully!

Ooh no, something went wrong!