30.09.2013 Views

Symposium - AIC

Symposium - AIC

Symposium - AIC

SHOW MORE
SHOW LESS

You also want an ePaper? Increase the reach of your titles

YUMPU automatically turns print PDFs into web optimized ePapers that Google loves.

Nicholas Riegel<br />

contrast to both tragedy and comedy, the chorus of satyrs in a satyr play takes an active part in the<br />

action of the drama; whereas, the chorus of tragedies and comedies is usually relegated to observation<br />

and commentary. And finally, the scene of satyr plays is generally “trees, caves, and mountains,”<br />

whereas the scene of tragedies is usually a palace, while the scene of comedies is usually the common<br />

spaces of a city.<br />

Though satyr plays are a distinct genre from comedy proper, it does not seem to me to follow<br />

necessarily that some of the things said about comedy cannot also be said about satyr play and vice<br />

versa. Even Seidensticker, who is adamant about the difference between satyr play and comedy, 7<br />

admits that they both have essentially the same function, namely “to get the audience to laugh.” 8 Thus<br />

just as Tragedy may be categorized as “that which is performed for the sake of fear and pity,” so<br />

perhaps we may group satyr play and comedy together under the heading “that which is performed for<br />

the sake of laughter.” And it is in this sense that what Socrates speaks about at the end of the<br />

<strong>Symposium</strong> as comedy, may also refer back to the speeches I have categorized as satyr plays in the<br />

two tetralogies.<br />

The second major objection may be that it is not at all clear that Plato believed there was a<br />

science of tragedy and comedy. At Republic 395A Socrates evinces clear awareness that as a matter<br />

of fact the same person does not write tragedies and comedies. This might be explained, as James<br />

Adam does, by saying that in Republic he is talking about what in fact is the case, whereas in<br />

<strong>Symposium</strong> he is talking about what should be the case. 9 The case of the Ion is more complex. For at<br />

Ion 534c Socrates seems to say that good poetry cannot be produced by a scientific method. But even<br />

if Plato believes that as a matter of fact, good poetry is not produced by scientific means, it seems to<br />

me, we may still ask why Plato seems to think in the <strong>Symposium</strong> that if it were produced<br />

scientifically, the same person would be able to write tragedies and comedies? It is true that, as Adam<br />

points out, 10 it is a Socratic principle that there should be one science for every pair of opposites, but<br />

we can still ask, what is it about tragedy and comedy in particular that makes Socrates think, at least<br />

in the <strong>Symposium</strong> that there could be a single science or craft of both?<br />

Having hopefully addressed these objections, let us turn now to the comparison of the two<br />

tetralogies: the first, we might call the ‘demotic tetralogy,’ and the second is the ‘philosophic<br />

tetralogy.’ In the first tetralogy we will see that each speech fails to adequately address the problems<br />

of love and life in their content. In the second, the methodology and content are correct – or so it<br />

would appear Plato thinks – but still, the speeches fail to bring the reader to the knowledge of the<br />

good and the solution to our mortality. After showing this, we will consider why Plato thinks neither<br />

tragedy nor comedy offers a solution to life, and why he thinks only philosophy can.<br />

III. THE FIRST, OR DEMOTIC TETRALOGY<br />

If we accept the bi-tetralogical structure of the <strong>Symposium</strong>, we can further analyze each tetralogy as<br />

follows: thesis, antithesis, development, and critique. Thus Phaedrus presents the thesis that love is<br />

good because his effects are good. Pausanias disagrees with Phaedrus that love’s effects are always<br />

good and thus feels the need to posit two kinds of love. Eryximachus agrees with Pausanias, but he<br />

goes further than any of the other speakers in explaining the essence of the good effects of love. At<br />

the basis, however, of all the first three speeches lies the assumption that love consists in two beings<br />

coming together and that the correct object of love is always another human being. Aristophanes<br />

makes this assumption explicit and perhaps also gently ridicules it.<br />

Phaedrus presents the thesis of the first tetralogy: the effects of love are good. Love, he<br />

argues, leads to virtuous activity. One would least of all like to be seen doing something shameful in<br />

the eyes of one’s lover. As proof he adduces the myths of Alcestis, Orpheus and Achilles. It was said<br />

that the all the speeches of the first tetralogy fail because they do not address the central problems of<br />

love, among which are the problems of suffering and death. But here, in the first speech of the first<br />

tetralogy Phaedrus explicitly refers and relies on myths surrounding the deaths of three persons. Even<br />

though Phaedrus does bring up the subject of death, it is clear that he does not do so in order to<br />

emphasize death as a central problem for the question of love and life; rather, he does so only in order<br />

to further his program of demonstrating the good effects of love. For a serious discussion of the<br />

7 “Even if (as is probable) the three dramatic genres arose from the same or closely related cultural contexts, in their fully<br />

developed literary forms each as its separate identity.” Ibid., 49.<br />

8 Ibid., 47.<br />

9 James Adam, The Republic of Plato: Edited with Critical Notes, Commentary and Appendices, 2 vols. (Cambridge:<br />

Cambridge University, 1902). ad loc.<br />

10 Ibid.<br />

279

Hooray! Your file is uploaded and ready to be published.

Saved successfully!

Ooh no, something went wrong!