30.09.2013 Views

Symposium - AIC

Symposium - AIC

Symposium - AIC

SHOW MORE
SHOW LESS

Create successful ePaper yourself

Turn your PDF publications into a flip-book with our unique Google optimized e-Paper software.

Jens Kristian Larsen<br />

philotimia, whereas the third part, 9 running from 209e5-212c3, finally, elaborates the effects of eros<br />

from the perspective of philosophia. Here I will limit myself to say a few words about the second and<br />

third parts, in particular about the relation between philotimia and philosophia we find therein. 10<br />

In both the second and the third part of Diotima’s speech we find a hierarchy of types of eros.<br />

These hierarchies are dependent on Diotima’s claim that eros, as desire for something, must be<br />

understood as broader than the erotic relation between human beings (205b4-c10): eros is, generally<br />

speaking, our desire to possess the good in order to become happy, a desire characterizing all human<br />

beings (204e1-205a8). But although all people naturally desire to possess the good, in order to<br />

become happy, different people regard different things as what is truly good. To illustrate this point,<br />

Diotima initially lists three types of desires, three kinds of eros, in addition to what is normally called<br />

love, namely a love of money-making, a love of gymnastics and a love of wisdom (205d4-5) that<br />

roughly seem to correspond to the three kinds of desires Socrates ascribed to the three parts of the<br />

soul in the Republic, that is the epithymic, the thymoedic and the rational parts (553c, 549a, 581b). 11<br />

Diotima then delivers two hierarchies of types of desire, one at the end of the second part of her<br />

speech, that is at 208e1-209a9, the other at the beginning of the third part, running from 210a4 to<br />

210e2. Both hierarchies begin by contrasting the types of desires to be placed within them with<br />

physical erotic desire, which in the Republic is determined as one of the characteristic desires of the<br />

epithymic part. As I see it, the first hierarchy is centred entirely on philotimia, which may be said to<br />

be the kind of eros which corresponds to the desire of what is in the Republic called the thymoeidic<br />

part, whereas the second culminates in the eros which corresponds to the leading desire of that part of<br />

the soul which in the Republic is called to logistikon.<br />

Prior to the first hierarchy, Diotima explains that the real motivation behind deeds performed<br />

as an expression of philotimia is a love of immortality, since immortality can supposedly be gained –<br />

so far as this is humanly possible - through an eternal renown for one’s virtue (208c1-e1). This<br />

motivation results in different psychic products, such as speeches about virtue (209b8), poetry (209a4-<br />

5, 209c7-d4) and lawgiving (209a6-8, 209d4-e4), which are supposedly the offspring of the virtues<br />

possessed by their creators. The third hierarchy, in contrast, regards this kind of striving for<br />

immortality as just a preliminary to philosophy (210a1-2, 210e5-6), which is the true striving for<br />

immortality, and here science (epistêmê, 210c6-d6) and the vision of true beauty is added to the list as<br />

higher kinds of eros.<br />

A full discussion of how these two hierarchies relate to each other lies beyond the scope of the<br />

present paper. Here I only wish to emphasize the following. The first hierarchy explicates different<br />

ways in which people seek eternal renown through psychic products that bear witness to their virtue,<br />

and this explains how philotimia drives people towards virtue, in a manner that closely resembles<br />

Phaedrus’ initial claim that philotimia leads us to imitate what is by nature best. 12 In contrast to<br />

Phaedrus, however, Diotima indicates that such activities have a further goal than virtue, namely<br />

eternal renown. 13 To people driven by philotimia, Diotima suggests, virtue is regarded as a means to<br />

an end, honour and renown, rather than as an end in itself. 14 In contrast, the second hierarchy makes<br />

clear that, in order to gain true virtue, and not just images (eidôla) of virtues (212a3-5), one must<br />

proceed from the love of bodies, of beautiful ways of living, and of the sciences, to a single science,<br />

namely the science about the beautiful (210d6-e1). It is only when one reaches this level of<br />

knowledge that one becomes virtuous and life becomes worth living (211d1-2). The second hierarchy<br />

thus makes clear that the virtues attested to by the deeds performed through philotimia are not true<br />

virtues.<br />

It is tempting to see a parallel between this and what Socrates claims in the Phaedo and the<br />

Republic, namely that political or popular virtue, the kind of virtue pursued by most gentlemen, is in<br />

fact not true virtue, because it is not grounded in knowledge or wisdom (phrônesis) which in turn<br />

9 There is a clear shift in Diotima’s speech at 209e5 which on the dramatic level is emphasized by the fact that Diotima,<br />

through the voice of Socrates, states that Socrates may no longer be able to follow her. As many commentators have pointed<br />

out, this shift is structured around the division between the lesser and the greater mysteries known from ??<br />

10 For a more elaborate discussion of how these relate, see Sheffield, op. Cit., 137-153<br />

11 See Francisco Lisi, ”Philosophische und tyrannische Liebe” in Plato’s <strong>Symposium</strong> – Proceedings of the fifth Symposim<br />

Platonicum Pragense, ed. A. Havlíček and M. Cajthaml. Prague, 2005, 182-183. See also Strauss, op. cit., 57. In contrast to<br />

Lisi I believe that the discussion of philotimia is not limited to the passage 208c1-e1 but continues till 209e4. For a similar<br />

reading, see Dorothe Frede, ”Eros als Verlangen nach Unsterblichkeit” in Platon. Symposion – Klassiker Auslegen 39, hg.<br />

Christoph Horn, Berlin: Akademie Verlag, 2012, 151-154.<br />

12 The connection with Phaedrus is emphasized by the fact that Diotima, in order to exemplify the deeds performed through<br />

philotimia, uses the same examples as Phaedrus had done earlier, compare 208d2—6 with 179b4-180b5.<br />

13 I have discussed the relation between Phaedrus’ and Diotima’s speeches at greater length in ”The love of the beloved” in<br />

Norsk Filosofisk Tidsskrift, Oslo: Universitetsforlaget, 2013, 81-83.<br />

14 Cf. Frede, op. cit., 151-152.<br />

171

Hooray! Your file is uploaded and ready to be published.

Saved successfully!

Ooh no, something went wrong!