22.06.2013 Views

Handbook of the History of Logic: - Fordham University Faculty

Handbook of the History of Logic: - Fordham University Faculty

Handbook of the History of Logic: - Fordham University Faculty

SHOW MORE
SHOW LESS

Create successful ePaper yourself

Turn your PDF publications into a flip-book with our unique Google optimized e-Paper software.

2 John Marenbon<br />

which was new; <strong>the</strong> position was consolidated in <strong>the</strong> three centuries followed, and<br />

logic continued to hold it until <strong>the</strong> end <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> Middle Ages. By studying logic in<br />

<strong>the</strong> early Middle Ages, <strong>the</strong>refore, we can hope to gain some understanding <strong>of</strong> how<br />

and why <strong>the</strong> subject had its special role within medieval education and thought.<br />

This aim calls for an approach ra<strong>the</strong>r different from that <strong>of</strong> most chapters in this<br />

handbook. Consideration <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> uses <strong>of</strong> logic and its connections with o<strong>the</strong>r subjects<br />

are as important here as <strong>the</strong> technicalities <strong>of</strong> logical doctrine. Indeed, <strong>the</strong>re<br />

is a sense in which <strong>the</strong> treatment here, just because it must fit into a handbook<br />

<strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> history <strong>of</strong> logic, must still remain over-<strong>the</strong>oretical and insufficiently historical.<br />

What is most needed to illuminate <strong>the</strong> broadly human importance <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong><br />

subject in this period (and in <strong>the</strong> twelfth to sixteenth centuries) is a social history<br />

<strong>of</strong> medieval logic, a type <strong>of</strong> study that has never until now been envisaged, let<br />

alone attempted. The following pages could be seen as prolegomena to part <strong>of</strong><br />

that enterprise.<br />

2 THE ANCIENT LATIN TRADITION<br />

When historians, using <strong>the</strong> medieval terminology, speak <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> logica vetus —<strong>the</strong><br />

corpus <strong>of</strong> ancient logical works used by Latin scholars in <strong>the</strong> early Middle Ages —<br />

<strong>the</strong>y sometimes take it in a narrow sense to mean just <strong>the</strong> three Greek logical texts,<br />

Porphyry’s Isagoge, and Aristotle’s Categories and On Interpretation, whichwere<br />

available in translation. From this perspective, it seems that <strong>the</strong> ancient Greek<br />

tradition <strong>of</strong> logic, though in a very curtailed form, is behind <strong>the</strong> work <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong><br />

early medieval logicians. But, by <strong>the</strong> eleventh century, <strong>the</strong> logical curriculum —<br />

<strong>the</strong> logica vetus in a wider and more useful sense — consisted <strong>of</strong> six works: <strong>the</strong><br />

three ancient Greek texts, and three textbooks written early in <strong>the</strong> sixth-century<br />

by <strong>the</strong> Latin thinker, Boethius: treatises on categorical syllogisms, hypo<strong>the</strong>tical<br />

syllogisms and on topical argument. Also attached to <strong>the</strong> curriculum, though<br />

more peripherally, was a work on definition attributed to Boethius but in fact<br />

by a Latin predecessor <strong>of</strong> his, Marius Victorinus, and Cicero’s Topics, along with<br />

Boethius’s commentary on it. And Boethius’s logical commentaries — two on <strong>the</strong><br />

Isagoge and On Interpretation, one on <strong>the</strong> Categories — were <strong>the</strong> tools with which<br />

<strong>the</strong>se three texts were studied. O<strong>the</strong>r Latin logical texts had been influential in<br />

<strong>the</strong> eighth to tenth centuries, although <strong>the</strong>y had mostly lost <strong>the</strong>ir importance by<br />

<strong>the</strong> eleventh: <strong>the</strong> Ten Categories, a paraphrase <strong>of</strong> Aristotle’s Categories from <strong>the</strong><br />

circle <strong>of</strong> Themistius, thought at <strong>the</strong> time to be by Augustine; Apuleius’s Peri<br />

Hermeneias; and <strong>the</strong> sections on logic in <strong>the</strong> encyclopaedias <strong>of</strong> Martianus Capella,<br />

Cassiodorus and Isidore <strong>of</strong> Seville. For all <strong>the</strong>se reasons, though much in early<br />

medieval logic goes back ultimately to Aristotle or to <strong>the</strong> ancient Peripatetics<br />

and <strong>the</strong> Neoplatonists who cultivated Aristotelian logic, <strong>the</strong>y drew more directly<br />

on a distinctively Latin tradition. It is here that we must begin. Boethius is<br />

<strong>the</strong> central figure but, as <strong>the</strong> list <strong>of</strong> names above suggests, his predecessors and<br />

successors should not be neglected.<br />

First, one preliminary, verbal note. Many <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> chapters or treatises discussed

Hooray! Your file is uploaded and ready to be published.

Saved successfully!

Ooh no, something went wrong!