22.06.2013 Views

Handbook of the History of Logic: - Fordham University Faculty

Handbook of the History of Logic: - Fordham University Faculty

Handbook of the History of Logic: - Fordham University Faculty

SHOW MORE
SHOW LESS

You also want an ePaper? Increase the reach of your titles

YUMPU automatically turns print PDFs into web optimized ePapers that Google loves.

Peter Abelard and His Contemporaries 103<br />

content and <strong>the</strong> sort <strong>of</strong> force with which it is asserted or o<strong>the</strong>rwise put forward.<br />

The content may be contained in an incomplete phrase like “running man” and<br />

put forward with no sort <strong>of</strong> force at all. But when a verb is in place to mark<br />

<strong>the</strong> relevant disposition <strong>of</strong> soul <strong>the</strong> corresponding force is brought to bear upon<br />

<strong>the</strong> content. In <strong>the</strong> case <strong>of</strong> assertion we have seen that this is a function not <strong>of</strong><br />

<strong>the</strong> mental acts <strong>of</strong> conception which constitute <strong>the</strong> basic signification <strong>of</strong> verbs and<br />

names alike, but ra<strong>the</strong>r a function <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> mental act supplementary to those, which<br />

marks <strong>the</strong> predicative relation and operates as a mode <strong>of</strong> that basic signification.<br />

Presumably this holds for <strong>the</strong> o<strong>the</strong>r kinds <strong>of</strong> complete phrase as well; in each<br />

case, it may be supposed, <strong>the</strong>ir distinctive force arises from a specific mode <strong>of</strong><br />

signification through a specific way <strong>of</strong> inflecting or o<strong>the</strong>rwise presenting <strong>the</strong> verb.<br />

So <strong>the</strong> sentential content <strong>of</strong> “Socrates is coming” is put here with assertive force,<br />

but could be put o<strong>the</strong>rwise with interrogative, imperative, precative or optative<br />

force (respectively: “Is Socrates coming?”, “Socrates, come!”, “Socrates, please<br />

come,” and “Would that Socrates would come”). 41<br />

For <strong>the</strong> logician, <strong>of</strong> course, it is only <strong>the</strong> first <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong>se five kinds <strong>of</strong> force —<br />

assertive — that constitutes an appropriate object <strong>of</strong> interest [Abelard, 1970, 152<br />

(27–8)], <strong>the</strong> o<strong>the</strong>rs being relegated to non-dialectical subject matters. Abelard<br />

has shed much light on how individual words combine to be productive <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong><br />

propositions <strong>the</strong>y compose. He must now turn to <strong>the</strong> special semantic properties<br />

<strong>of</strong> propositions <strong>the</strong>mselves. The point <strong>of</strong> departure is <strong>the</strong> Boethian definition <strong>of</strong><br />

<strong>the</strong> proposition as that which “signifies a truth or a falsehood” [Abelard, 1970, p.<br />

153 (33); Boethius, 1990, p. 2]. To grasp <strong>the</strong> special character <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> proposition<br />

as a semantic unit accordingly requires some insight into what is meant by “true”<br />

and “false.”<br />

To this end, Abelard suggests a key distinction: “Just as names and verbs have a<br />

tw<strong>of</strong>old signification — <strong>of</strong> things and understandings — we also grant that propositions<br />

have a tw<strong>of</strong>old signification: according to <strong>the</strong> understandings composed <strong>of</strong><br />

<strong>the</strong> understandings <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong>ir parts, and according to <strong>the</strong>ir dicta” [Abelard, 1927,<br />

p. 367 (9–12), Abelard, 2006, 04.26]. Individual names generate understandings<br />

and name things, and in some sense <strong>the</strong> same can be said <strong>of</strong> propositions. But<br />

what has so far been said about <strong>the</strong> semantics <strong>of</strong> stating has focussed on understandings<br />

only. The key question has been how <strong>the</strong> combination <strong>of</strong> words into<br />

phrases is made meaningful by <strong>the</strong> combination <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong>ir associated understandings<br />

into larger conceptual structures. But this cannot be <strong>the</strong> whole picture. To satisfy<br />

<strong>the</strong>ir full semantic function, names are normally expected to refer. Likewise,<br />

to satisfy <strong>the</strong>ir full semantic function, propositions are normally expected to be<br />

true. Just as <strong>the</strong>re must be something for <strong>the</strong> name to refer to, <strong>the</strong>re must also<br />

147]. Martin Lenz argues that for Abelard <strong>the</strong> true criterion <strong>of</strong> completeness is not <strong>the</strong> fact that<br />

<strong>the</strong> listener does not expect to hear more (<strong>the</strong> “suspense-criterion”), or <strong>the</strong> fact that <strong>the</strong> phrase<br />

contains a finite verb (<strong>the</strong> “grammatical criterion”), or <strong>the</strong> fact that it signifies a predication<br />

(<strong>the</strong> “logical criterion”), but <strong>the</strong> fact that one <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> propositional attitudes is expressed [Lenz,<br />

2005, pp. 381, 383].<br />

41 For Abelard’s examples (which do not, as mine do, use <strong>the</strong> same content throughout) see<br />

[Abelard, 1970, p. 151 (6–15)].

Hooray! Your file is uploaded and ready to be published.

Saved successfully!

Ooh no, something went wrong!