22.06.2013 Views

Handbook of the History of Logic: - Fordham University Faculty

Handbook of the History of Logic: - Fordham University Faculty

Handbook of the History of Logic: - Fordham University Faculty

SHOW MORE
SHOW LESS

You also want an ePaper? Increase the reach of your titles

YUMPU automatically turns print PDFs into web optimized ePapers that Google loves.

580 Mikko Yrjönsuuri<br />

but even with <strong>the</strong> truth-predicate analogous paradoxes were constructed in significantly<br />

differing ways. The semantic paradoxes <strong>of</strong> self-reference seem to have<br />

been discussed in both Arabic and Latin logic well before <strong>the</strong> thirteenth century<br />

so that <strong>the</strong> standard example was ‘what I utter is false’, but various authors developed<br />

versions that in many cases were interestingly different in terms <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong><br />

solutions given for <strong>the</strong> core paradox. Roughly at <strong>the</strong> beginning <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> fourteenth<br />

century treatments <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> topic became really a flourishing genre <strong>of</strong> logic. The<br />

most original work seems to have been done in <strong>the</strong> 1320s and 1330s in Oxford<br />

by authors like Richard Kilvington, William Heytesbury and Roger Swyneshed.<br />

Especially Thomas Bradwardine’s treatment accrued well-deserved fame in <strong>the</strong><br />

following centuries. These logicians really can be said to have undertaken <strong>the</strong> task<br />

<strong>of</strong> giving a consistent, <strong>the</strong>oretically satisfactory solution to <strong>the</strong> Liar paradox and<br />

its associates ra<strong>the</strong>r than simply having <strong>the</strong> interest <strong>of</strong> studying various logical<br />

aspects <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> Liar and o<strong>the</strong>r congenial paradoxes.<br />

In <strong>the</strong> following I will go through a selection <strong>of</strong> medieval texts. The choice <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong><br />

texts is not straightforwardly based on <strong>the</strong> historical importance or even quality<br />

in logic. The aim is, ra<strong>the</strong>r, that <strong>the</strong> sample gives a picture <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> multiplicity and<br />

<strong>the</strong>oretical richness <strong>of</strong> this particular medieval discussion.<br />

INSOLUBILIA MONACENSIA<br />

The oldest known Latin tract dedicated to <strong>the</strong> paradoxes <strong>of</strong> self-reference is an<br />

anonymous text written about at <strong>the</strong> end <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> twelfth century, called Insolubilia<br />

Monacensia according to <strong>the</strong> current location <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> manuscript in Munich.<br />

Scholars know about occasional references to <strong>the</strong> Liar paradox already long before<br />

that, like in Adam <strong>of</strong> Balsham’s Ars disserendi, which was written in 1132 [Adam<br />

<strong>of</strong> Balsham, 1956, 107]. However, <strong>the</strong> scarcity <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> surviving early treatments <strong>of</strong><br />

<strong>the</strong> paradox has made it difficult to give a story how <strong>the</strong> medieval Latin discussions<br />

got started. One alternative is that <strong>the</strong>y originate from Byzantine Greek or<br />

medieval Arabic logical texts, which are not known ei<strong>the</strong>r. 1<br />

In any case, Insolubilia Monacensia presents a <strong>the</strong>ory that is already relatively<br />

developed. The word for <strong>the</strong>se paradoxes is insolubilia, or “insolubles”, and <strong>the</strong><br />

author explains that this is due to <strong>the</strong> difficulty in giving a truth value evaluation<br />

<strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> paradoxical sentences. In a manner typical for medieval logicians, he puts<br />

<strong>the</strong> problem in a disputational context. “A solution is,” as he says, “an appropriate<br />

determination <strong>of</strong> a thing”, which means that <strong>the</strong> semantic value <strong>of</strong> a proposition<br />

is evaluated in a satisfactory way, typically by saying “yes” (ita) or“no”(non),<br />

or “it is true” or “it is false” [De Rijk, 1966, 104]. That <strong>the</strong> author is thinking<br />

<strong>of</strong> disputations in fairly technical terms becomes obvious from his comment that<br />

1 Cf. [De Rijk, 1966, 83–86, 103]; edition <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> Insolubilia Monacensia on pp. 104–115.<br />

The text has been discussed also by, e.g. [Spade, 1973]; see also [Spade, 1987; Martin, 1993;<br />

Bottin, 1976]. For a listing <strong>of</strong> medieval texts, see [Spade, 1975]. For o<strong>the</strong>r interesting early<br />

treatments, see [Braakhuis, 1967; De Rijk, 1976; Roure, 1970]. Discussions are also to be found<br />

in commentaries on Aristotle’s Sophistical Refutations.

Hooray! Your file is uploaded and ready to be published.

Saved successfully!

Ooh no, something went wrong!