22.06.2013 Views

Handbook of the History of Logic: - Fordham University Faculty

Handbook of the History of Logic: - Fordham University Faculty

Handbook of the History of Logic: - Fordham University Faculty

SHOW MORE
SHOW LESS

You also want an ePaper? Increase the reach of your titles

YUMPU automatically turns print PDFs into web optimized ePapers that Google loves.

<strong>Logic</strong> in <strong>the</strong> 14 th Century after Ockham 457<br />

Thomas <strong>of</strong> Cleves’s ‘fourth’ mode <strong>of</strong> personal supposition, but to him this is not<br />

a fourth but ra<strong>the</strong>r a third mode, because he does not recognize merely confused<br />

personal supposition. While this may seem an awkward position at first sight, it<br />

is not altoge<strong>the</strong>r implausible considering that, for Vincent Ferrer, and following<br />

very early (12 th and 13 th century) notions <strong>of</strong> supposition, it is only <strong>the</strong> subject <strong>of</strong><br />

a categorical proposition that has supposition, not <strong>the</strong> predicate (cf. [Trentman,<br />

1977, 89-92]). Given that, usually, merely confused personal supposition concerns<br />

<strong>the</strong> supposition <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> predicate (in particular in universal affirmative propositions),<br />

if one does not attribute supposition to <strong>the</strong> predicate, <strong>the</strong>n <strong>the</strong>re may seem<br />

to be no need to recognize merely confused personal supposition.<br />

But <strong>the</strong> fact that Ferrer recognized collective supposition poses a historiographic<br />

problem. While <strong>the</strong>re is a clear line <strong>of</strong> continuity between <strong>the</strong> o<strong>the</strong>r authors mentioned<br />

so far (Maulfelt, Albert <strong>of</strong> Saxony, Thomas <strong>of</strong> Cleves, all roughly belonging<br />

to <strong>the</strong> same Parisian nominalist tradition), Vincent Ferrer was, as already mentioned,<br />

educated in Spain, and saw himself as belonging to a Thomist tradition,<br />

thus completely out <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> circle <strong>of</strong> influence <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> nominalist tradition. Read<br />

[1991a, 74] argues that Ferrer’s treatise ‘does not read like that <strong>of</strong> an author inventing<br />

an original <strong>the</strong>ory’; that is, presumably collective supposition was already<br />

a recognized mode <strong>of</strong> supposition in <strong>the</strong> tradition within which he was schooled.<br />

We could thus have two independent ‘inventions’ <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> concept <strong>of</strong> collective supposition.<br />

But our knowledge <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> 14 th century Spanish logical tradition is as <strong>of</strong><br />

yet still insufficient in order to tell us whe<strong>the</strong>r <strong>the</strong> concept <strong>of</strong> collective supposition<br />

was indeed independently developed within this tradition (which seems unlikely,<br />

given <strong>the</strong> coincidence in terminology), or whe<strong>the</strong>r <strong>the</strong>re were earlier points <strong>of</strong> contact<br />

between <strong>the</strong> two traditions in such a way that <strong>the</strong>re might have been influence<br />

in one direction or in <strong>the</strong> o<strong>the</strong>r (or both).<br />

In sum, <strong>the</strong> debate concerning nominal conjunctive descent and a fourth mode<br />

<strong>of</strong> supposition was a heated one in <strong>the</strong> second half <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> 14 th century. While it is<br />

fair to say that <strong>the</strong> majority <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> authors preferred to maintain <strong>the</strong> traditional<br />

scheme with three modes <strong>of</strong> common personal supposition (see [Ashworth, 1978]),<br />

for <strong>the</strong> sake <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong>oretical parsimony and probably also out <strong>of</strong> respect for <strong>the</strong> tradition,<br />

many authors never<strong>the</strong>less recognized <strong>the</strong> fourth kind <strong>of</strong> descent. But all<br />

in all, considered from a systematic point <strong>of</strong> view, it seems that supposition <strong>the</strong>ory<br />

containing four modes <strong>of</strong> personal supposition is indeed a more sophisticated<br />

version <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> traditional <strong>the</strong>ory: it respects <strong>the</strong> logical symmetry <strong>of</strong> nominal and<br />

propositional descent, and it allows for a very intuitive account <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> semantics<br />

<strong>of</strong> some terms (even if some <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong>m can also be accounted for with only <strong>the</strong> three<br />

traditional kinds <strong>of</strong> descent).<br />

2.1.3 Different modes <strong>of</strong> supposition also for material supposition<br />

In <strong>the</strong> traditional formulations <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong>ories <strong>of</strong> supposition, in particular with <strong>the</strong><br />

13 th century summulists (William <strong>of</strong> Sherwood, Peter <strong>of</strong> Spain), but also with<br />

authors <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> first half <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> 14 th century such as Ockham and Buridan, <strong>the</strong>re

Hooray! Your file is uploaded and ready to be published.

Saved successfully!

Ooh no, something went wrong!