22.06.2013 Views

Handbook of the History of Logic: - Fordham University Faculty

Handbook of the History of Logic: - Fordham University Faculty

Handbook of the History of Logic: - Fordham University Faculty

SHOW MORE
SHOW LESS

You also want an ePaper? Increase the reach of your titles

YUMPU automatically turns print PDFs into web optimized ePapers that Google loves.

Medieval Modal Theories and Modal <strong>Logic</strong> 543<br />

if something contained under <strong>the</strong> predicate term is unchangeable with<br />

respect to something contained under <strong>the</strong> subject term, as long as this<br />

exists. This holds when <strong>the</strong> terms are common. When <strong>the</strong> terms are<br />

singular, it is required that what is signified by one is not changeable<br />

with respect to what is signified by <strong>the</strong> o<strong>the</strong>r, as long as this exists. 130<br />

Unchangeable features signified by common terms may be transcendental properties,<br />

such as ‘something’, substantial forms, properties based on <strong>the</strong> species nature<br />

<strong>of</strong> things, such as ‘mortal’, ‘living’, or o<strong>the</strong>r inseparable attributes. 131 Divided<br />

affirmative necessity propositions with common or singular terms express that<br />

things under a necessarily predicated term are in various ways <strong>the</strong> same as actual<br />

things under a subject term, as long as both exist. 132 Campsall believes that<br />

this reading <strong>of</strong> divided necessity propositions explains why <strong>the</strong>y are regulated by<br />

<strong>the</strong> Aristotelian rules <strong>of</strong> conversion. The strict restriction to actual things is not<br />

separately explained since Campsall probably thought that Aristotelian necessity<br />

premises should be treated in this way and that only actual things can have necessary<br />

properties. Much attention is paid to <strong>the</strong> example ‘A pale Socrates is necessarily<br />

Socrates’. This is said to be false for <strong>the</strong> reason that what <strong>the</strong> accidental<br />

subject term signifies is not an invariable characterization <strong>of</strong> Socrates. 133 Campsall<br />

does not deal with <strong>the</strong> traditional universal or particular counter-examples,<br />

thinking that <strong>the</strong>y can be analysed into <strong>the</strong> conjunctions or disjunctions <strong>of</strong> singular<br />

propositions with terms standing for accidental combinations.<br />

The equation <strong>of</strong> necessity with unchanging relations pushes Campsall’s <strong>the</strong>ory<br />

toward <strong>the</strong> temporal frequency approaches <strong>of</strong> necessity. It is also characterized by<br />

some versions <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> principles that <strong>the</strong> present is necessary and that possibility<br />

implies actuality. Let us take a look at his pro<strong>of</strong>s <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> conversion <strong>of</strong> divided<br />

necessity propositions. According to Campsall, ‘Every/some B is necessarily A’<br />

is converted into ‘some A is necessarily B’, because <strong>the</strong> negation <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> converted<br />

proposition ‘Every A is possibly not B’ is not compatible with <strong>the</strong> proposition to<br />

be converted. This is allegedly shown by <strong>the</strong> fact that were <strong>the</strong> negation true, a<br />

particular being, say c, whichisB and necessarily A wouldbepossiblynotB.<br />

This is said to be impossible, apparently because c is necessarily B qua being<br />

unchangingly A. 134 Campsall’s pro<strong>of</strong> <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> convertibility <strong>of</strong> universal negative<br />

divided necessity proposition is similar — this time he states that ‘this consequence<br />

is necessary: c can be one <strong>of</strong> those which are now contained under B; <strong>the</strong>refore it<br />

130 6.25 (122-3).<br />

131 5.43-5 (112-3); 9.18 (157).<br />

132 For <strong>the</strong> actuality condition, see 5.40 (111); divided negative propositions express that <strong>the</strong><br />

things under <strong>the</strong> terms are necessarily separated (5.38 (110)).<br />

133 6.25-31 (122-5).<br />

134 6.22 (121-2). According to Lagerlund, Campsall assumes that if c is possibly not B now, it<br />

is not B now (2001, 68). Campsall explicitly denies this principle later (19.21 (297)) and <strong>the</strong><br />

argument can be understood as indicated above. Campsall maintains, however, that if c is not<br />

B now, it is necessarily not B now (5.50 (114)). If all negative propositions about actual things<br />

are necessary, it is clear that <strong>the</strong>re are no simultaneous de re alternatives. In this sense actuality<br />

implies necessity. It seems that Campsall was not fully aware <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> problems embedded in his<br />

formulations.

Hooray! Your file is uploaded and ready to be published.

Saved successfully!

Ooh no, something went wrong!