22.06.2013 Views

Handbook of the History of Logic: - Fordham University Faculty

Handbook of the History of Logic: - Fordham University Faculty

Handbook of the History of Logic: - Fordham University Faculty

SHOW MORE
SHOW LESS

You also want an ePaper? Increase the reach of your titles

YUMPU automatically turns print PDFs into web optimized ePapers that Google loves.

1.7 Essentialist Assumptions<br />

Medieval Modal Theories and Modal <strong>Logic</strong> 529<br />

In his treatise On Hypo<strong>the</strong>tical Syllogisms Boethius speaks about two kinds <strong>of</strong><br />

conditionals which express a necessary consequence between <strong>the</strong> antecedent and<br />

<strong>the</strong> consequent. The consequence is accidentally necessary when <strong>the</strong> antecedent<br />

and consequent are immutably true but have no internal link between <strong>the</strong>m, for<br />

example ‘If fire is hot, <strong>the</strong> heavens are spherical’. In a non-accidental consequence,<br />

which Boethius calls natural, <strong>the</strong>re is a conceptual connection between <strong>the</strong> parts;<br />

for example, ‘If something is human, it is an animal’. Abelard also teaches that<br />

a genuine conditional expresses a necessary consequence in which <strong>the</strong> antecedent<br />

<strong>of</strong> itself requires <strong>the</strong> consequent. These were taken to express immutable laws <strong>of</strong><br />

nature derivable from <strong>the</strong> nature <strong>of</strong> things. 81 A related distinction between per se<br />

and per accidens necessary propositions was employed in mid-thirteenth century<br />

discussions <strong>of</strong> modal conversion and modal syllogistic. Robert Kilwardby states<br />

that some necessary connections between terms are merely accidentally necessary<br />

in <strong>the</strong> sense that <strong>the</strong> things signified are inseparable. These necessities are not<br />

dealt with in modal syllogistic <strong>the</strong> necessity propositions <strong>of</strong> which express per se<br />

necessities explained in Posterior Analytics I.4. The first type is said to occur<br />

when <strong>the</strong> definition <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> subject includes <strong>the</strong> predicate and <strong>the</strong> second type<br />

when <strong>the</strong> definition <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> predicate includes <strong>the</strong> subject. Typical per se necessary<br />

propositions were those expressing <strong>the</strong> properties determined by <strong>the</strong> substantial<br />

form <strong>of</strong> a subject or, as in <strong>the</strong> second class, o<strong>the</strong>r features based on <strong>the</strong> genusspecies<br />

structure. Terms <strong>the</strong>mselves were necessary if <strong>the</strong>y stood necessarily for<br />

what <strong>the</strong>y signified, for example ‘horse’. O<strong>the</strong>r terms were accidental, for example<br />

‘white’ or ‘walking’. (See also 2.4 below.)<br />

Necessary propositions which were not per se necessary were <strong>of</strong>ten exemplified<br />

by propositions about inseparable accidents. In <strong>the</strong> Isagoge, Porphyry defines <strong>the</strong><br />

inseparable accident as something which cannot actually be removed from its subject<br />

though <strong>the</strong> subject can be conceived <strong>of</strong> without it (3.5-6). The idea <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong><br />

degrees <strong>of</strong> necessity and impossibility was also developed in late ancient discussions<br />

<strong>of</strong> indirect pro<strong>of</strong>s and impossible hypo<strong>the</strong>ses. In order to defend Aristotle’s<br />

indirect pro<strong>of</strong>s with impossible premises, Alexander <strong>of</strong> Aphrodisias argued that<br />

Aristotle had in mind impossibilities which were not nonsensical. 82 Some late<br />

ancient authors were interested in impossible hypo<strong>the</strong>ses as tools for conceptual<br />

which does not imply that future contingent statements are true or false. This was an exceptional<br />

view. See C. Schabel, Theology at Paris, 1316-1345: Peter Auriol and <strong>the</strong> Problem <strong>of</strong> Divine<br />

Foreknowledge and Future Contingents (Aldershot: Ashgate, 2001).<br />

81 Boethius, De hypo<strong>the</strong>ticis syllogismis, I.3.7; Abelard, Dialectica, 253.28-30; 279.12-14;<br />

280,12-18; 283.37-284.17; see also Garland <strong>the</strong> Computist, Dialectica, 141.7-22. Some later<br />

twelfth-century masters regarded <strong>the</strong> principle that <strong>the</strong> antecedent is not true without <strong>the</strong> consequent<br />

as a sufficient condition for <strong>the</strong> truth <strong>of</strong> a conditional and accepted <strong>the</strong> so-called paradoxes<br />

<strong>of</strong> implication. See C.J. Martin, ‘<strong>Logic</strong>’ in J. E. Brower and K. Guilfoy (eds.), The Cambridge<br />

Companion to Abelard (Cambridge: Cambridge <strong>University</strong> Press, 2004), 164-5, 179-81.<br />

82 See <strong>the</strong> report in Simplicius, In Aristotelis Physicorum libros quattuor posteriores commentaria,<br />

ed. H. Diels, Commentaria in Aristotelem Graeca 10 (Berlin: Reimer, 1895), 1039.13-14,<br />

26-7; translated by C. Hagen in Simplicius, On Aristotle’s Physics 7 (London: Duckworth, 1994),<br />

105.

Hooray! Your file is uploaded and ready to be published.

Saved successfully!

Ooh no, something went wrong!