22.06.2013 Views

Handbook of the History of Logic: - Fordham University Faculty

Handbook of the History of Logic: - Fordham University Faculty

Handbook of the History of Logic: - Fordham University Faculty

SHOW MORE
SHOW LESS

You also want an ePaper? Increase the reach of your titles

YUMPU automatically turns print PDFs into web optimized ePapers that Google loves.

<strong>Logic</strong> and Theories <strong>of</strong> Meaning . . . 369<br />

but something in between univocal and equivocal: being was said to belong to<br />

accidents secundum prius et posterius. 117 The discussion was fur<strong>the</strong>r complicated<br />

by a passage in Aristotle’s Physics where he says that “equivocations are hidden<br />

in genera”. 118<br />

The result is that we find a threefold division <strong>of</strong> analogy in <strong>the</strong> late 13 th century<br />

Elenchi commentaries. 119 In all three types speaking according to priority and<br />

posteriority is involved:<br />

1. The first type <strong>of</strong> analogy occurs in <strong>the</strong> relation <strong>of</strong> a genus to its species. For<br />

example, ‘animal’ is an analogical term that can be predicated <strong>of</strong> rational and<br />

non-rational animals alike. The two species participate equally in <strong>the</strong> ratio<br />

<strong>of</strong> genus (i.e. ‘animal’ means <strong>the</strong> same in both cases), but since one species<br />

is more noble than <strong>the</strong> o<strong>the</strong>r (rationality is a habit and non-rationality <strong>the</strong><br />

absence <strong>of</strong> a habit), one species is said to fall under <strong>the</strong> genus primarily (per<br />

prius) and <strong>the</strong> o<strong>the</strong>r secondarily (per posterius). This type <strong>of</strong> analogy is<br />

called univocation, because both analogates participate equally in <strong>the</strong> same<br />

characteristic.<br />

2. The second type <strong>of</strong> analogy occurs when <strong>the</strong> analogates participate in <strong>the</strong><br />

same characteristic (ratio), but not equally. This is <strong>the</strong> case with being (ens)<br />

in relation to substance and accident. Substances participate directly and<br />

primarily (per prius) in being, whereas accidents do so only immediately and<br />

secondarily (per posterius), i.e. by means <strong>of</strong> substances, since accidents do<br />

not exist separately from <strong>the</strong> substance in which <strong>the</strong>y inhere. This type <strong>of</strong><br />

analogy is nei<strong>the</strong>r strictly univocal, nor strictly equivocal, but something in<br />

between, because <strong>the</strong>y share more than just a name.<br />

3. The third type <strong>of</strong> analogy is identical to deliberate equivocation. It occurs<br />

when <strong>the</strong> analogates share only a name, as is <strong>the</strong> case with ‘healthy’ said <strong>of</strong><br />

an animal, urine, a diet and a medicine. ‘Healthy’ signifies primarily (primo<br />

et simpliciter) a healthy animal and it signifies <strong>the</strong> o<strong>the</strong>r things secondarily<br />

through attribution (per attributionem) to <strong>the</strong> first thing.<br />

This threefold division <strong>of</strong> analogy and <strong>the</strong> language in which it is put suggests that<br />

<strong>the</strong> authors were interested in an ontologically based division. In <strong>the</strong>ir view, <strong>the</strong><br />

hierarchy <strong>of</strong> analogical terms is related to types <strong>of</strong> participation. Also Aquinas held<br />

that analogical predication depends on natures being shared in prior and posterior<br />

ways. 120 Duns Scotus criticizes this view in his commentaries on <strong>the</strong> Categories<br />

and <strong>the</strong> Sophistici Elenchi. Scotus argued that analogy is possible in <strong>the</strong> order<br />

<strong>of</strong> things, but that words signify according to <strong>the</strong>ir imposition. The process <strong>of</strong><br />

imposition is voluntary and does not allow for an ordering among significations<br />

117 See e.g. Algazel’s logic, as cited in Ashworth [1992, p. 108].<br />

118 Aristotle, Physics 7 (249a22-5).<br />

119 The division presented here comes from Incerti auctores, qu. 823, [ed. Ebbesen, pp. 314–<br />

317]. The examples are mine. See also: Ashworth [1992, pp. 119–120].<br />

120 Ashworth [1992, p. 127].

Hooray! Your file is uploaded and ready to be published.

Saved successfully!

Ooh no, something went wrong!