22.06.2013 Views

Handbook of the History of Logic: - Fordham University Faculty

Handbook of the History of Logic: - Fordham University Faculty

Handbook of the History of Logic: - Fordham University Faculty

SHOW MORE
SHOW LESS

Create successful ePaper yourself

Turn your PDF publications into a flip-book with our unique Google optimized e-Paper software.

554 Simo Knuuttila<br />

propositions are necessary, possible, or impossible depending on whe<strong>the</strong>r <strong>the</strong>y can<br />

or cannot be true or false. Only those propositions were counted as modal, however,<br />

which included modal terms connected to <strong>the</strong> copula (divided modals) or<br />

connected by <strong>the</strong> copula to propositions or to dicta (compound modals). 178<br />

The conversions <strong>of</strong> compound necessity and possibility propositions with respect<br />

to <strong>the</strong> dictum were not considered problematic. As in Campsall, <strong>the</strong>se were said to<br />

hold by <strong>the</strong> rules that if <strong>the</strong> antecedent <strong>of</strong> a valid consequence is possible <strong>the</strong>n <strong>the</strong><br />

consequent is possible, and if <strong>the</strong> antecedent is <strong>of</strong> necessity <strong>the</strong>n <strong>the</strong> consequent<br />

is <strong>of</strong> necessity or, as with simple conversions, if one <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> convertibles is possible<br />

(necessary) <strong>the</strong>n <strong>the</strong> o<strong>the</strong>r is possible (necessary). Of compound contingency<br />

propositions only those with simply convertible dicta are converted; <strong>the</strong> rule that if<br />

<strong>the</strong> antecedent is contingent <strong>the</strong>n <strong>the</strong> consequent is contingent is not valid. 179 The<br />

whole logic <strong>of</strong> compound modal propositions was in fact based on <strong>the</strong> Aristotelian<br />

principles for propositional modal logic which, as noted above, were widely known<br />

in early medieval logic as well. When modal syllogisms were regarded as syllogisms<br />

with respect to <strong>the</strong> dicta, connecting <strong>the</strong> mode ‘necessary’ with <strong>the</strong> premises and<br />

conclusions <strong>of</strong> valid assertoric syllogisms yielded valid modal syllogisms. This was<br />

based on (4) and <strong>the</strong> rule that if <strong>the</strong> conjuncts are necessary, <strong>the</strong> conjunction is<br />

necessary. Uniform syllogisms consisting <strong>of</strong> compound contingency or possibility<br />

modals were not considered valid, because <strong>the</strong> compossibility <strong>of</strong> two possible<br />

premises was not assured. Ockham and Pseudo-Scotus remark that because de<br />

dicto necessities are compossible with any de dicto possibilities or contingencies,<br />

mixed compound necessity and possibility or contingency syllogisms with possible<br />

or contingent conclusions are valid. Buridan did not mention this. 180<br />

The main object <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> fourteenth-century modal logic was <strong>the</strong> <strong>the</strong>ory <strong>of</strong> divided<br />

modals. Some treatises include discussions in which <strong>the</strong> logical relations<br />

between various divided modal propositions were codified in <strong>the</strong> same way as<br />

<strong>the</strong> relations between <strong>the</strong> types <strong>of</strong> assertoric propositions in <strong>the</strong> square <strong>of</strong> opposition.<br />

Buridan taught that <strong>the</strong>re were two types <strong>of</strong> copula, <strong>the</strong> affirmative ‘is’<br />

and <strong>the</strong> negative ‘is-not’, and that modality was part <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> copula in divided<br />

modal propositions. Combining <strong>the</strong> equivalences between quantifying words with<br />

negations with equivalent modalities, Buridan arranged divided modals into eight<br />

groups <strong>of</strong> nine equivalent formulae. In <strong>the</strong> Summulae, <strong>the</strong>se groups are presented<br />

in a diagram showing <strong>the</strong> relations <strong>of</strong> contradiction, contrariety, sub-contrariety,<br />

and sub-alternation between <strong>the</strong>m. 181<br />

178BC II.1, 56; PS I.25, 309; William Ockham., Expositio in librum Perihermenias Aristotelis,<br />

ed. A. Gambatese and S. Brown, Opera philosophica II (St. Bonaventure: St. Bonaventure<br />

<strong>University</strong>, 1978), 459-66.<br />

179OSL II.24-5, 27, 327-8, 330-31, 334; BC II.7.12-14, 72-4; PS I.25, 310; I.30, 319.<br />

180PS I.27, 313; I.33, 323; OSL III-1.20, 412-13; III-1.23, 419; III-1.44, 474; III-1.47, 479; BC<br />

IV.1.1, 113.<br />

181For this octagon <strong>of</strong> opposition, see Summulae de dialectica I.8.4-7 and <strong>the</strong> diagram in Questiones<br />

longe super librum Perihermeneias II.9, 87; see also Hughes 1989, 109-10; E. Karger, ‘Buridan’s<br />

Theory <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> <strong>Logic</strong>al Relations between General Modal Formulae’ in H.A.G. Braakhuis<br />

and C.H. Kneepkens (eds.), Aristotle’s Peri hermeneias in <strong>the</strong> Latin Middle Ages, Artistarium<br />

supplementa 10 (Groningen – Haren: Ingenium Publishers, 2003), 429-44.

Hooray! Your file is uploaded and ready to be published.

Saved successfully!

Ooh no, something went wrong!