22.06.2013 Views

Handbook of the History of Logic: - Fordham University Faculty

Handbook of the History of Logic: - Fordham University Faculty

Handbook of the History of Logic: - Fordham University Faculty

SHOW MORE
SHOW LESS

Create successful ePaper yourself

Turn your PDF publications into a flip-book with our unique Google optimized e-Paper software.

Medieval Modal Theories and Modal <strong>Logic</strong> 539<br />

<strong>the</strong> divided sense. One <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> problems <strong>of</strong> his modal syllogistics is that reading<br />

<strong>the</strong>se conversion rules in <strong>the</strong> divided sense leads to obvious difficulties: <strong>the</strong> actuality<br />

<strong>of</strong> subjects changes into necessity and possibility into actuality. Contrary to<br />

what one might expect, <strong>the</strong> relationship between compound and divided modalities<br />

was not dealt with in mid-thirteenth-century discussions <strong>of</strong> Aristotle’s rules,<br />

<strong>the</strong>se being associated with various philosophical ideas <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> nature <strong>of</strong> necessity<br />

and contingency. Many authors tried to redefine syllogistic necessity propositions<br />

in a way which would match <strong>the</strong> conversion rules. This took place in treating some<br />

<strong>of</strong>ten repeated counter-examples, such as<br />

(17) Everything literate is necessarily a human being<br />

(18) Everything healthy (or awake) is necessarily an animal<br />

or<br />

(19) Everything white is necessarily a body.<br />

It was considered an obvious fact that no animal is necessarily healthy or that<br />

‘some animal is healthy’ is not a necessary truth. Some authors argued that in<br />

examples like (17)–(19) <strong>the</strong> denominative subject terms refer to things which are<br />

qualified by non-essential forms and that <strong>the</strong>se terms should be treated in <strong>the</strong> same<br />

way when <strong>the</strong>y are predicates. 114 ‘An animal is necessarily healthy’ is taken to<br />

mean that an animal is necessarily that which is healthy. Accordingly, (17) could<br />

be read: ‘Every literate being is necessarily a member <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> class <strong>of</strong> human beings’,<br />

but even <strong>the</strong>n <strong>the</strong> conversion ‘Some human beings are necessarily members <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong><br />

class <strong>of</strong> literate beings’ is false, if this is not understood, as Lambert <strong>of</strong> Auxerre<br />

suggests, to mean that some human beings are necessarily those who are literate,<br />

that is, human beings.<br />

Robert Kilwardby, after mentioning this pretty artificial idea, moves to a ‘more<br />

probable’ interpretation which is based on <strong>the</strong> view that convertible necessity<br />

premises in modal syllogistic are necessity propositions per se and not per accidens,<br />

like (17)–(19), which are not convertible. In affirmative necessity propositions<br />

per se, <strong>the</strong> subject is per se connected to <strong>the</strong> predicate. In negative necessity<br />

propositions per se, <strong>the</strong> subject is apparently per se incompatible with <strong>the</strong> predicate.<br />

In accidental necessity propositions, <strong>the</strong> connection is not based on a per se<br />

inherence or repugnance. 115 In explaining <strong>the</strong> notion <strong>of</strong> per se later in his work,<br />

114 See Lambert <strong>of</strong> Auxerre, <strong>Logic</strong>a 39.1-41; Robert Kilwardby, In Pr. an. 7ra; Roger Bacon,<br />

Summulae dialectices III.1.2, 58, 60; cf. In Pr. an. (Orléans) f. 180b.<br />

115 In Pr. an. 7ra-b; cf. 45rb for essential negative propositions. Kilwardby’s concludes in 7rb:<br />

‘Therefore, when Aristotle teaches that necessity propositions are convertible, he means that<br />

only per se necessity propositions are convertible’. Aristotle did not say this; Kilwardby followed<br />

<strong>the</strong> medieval commentator habit <strong>of</strong> maintaining that what commentators found reasonable was<br />

what Aristotle said or meant. Kilwardby seems to assume that syllogistic necessity propositions<br />

should be taken in <strong>the</strong> divided sense or at least not in <strong>the</strong> composite sense (27va). For per se<br />

necessity in Kilwardby, see also Lagerlund 2000, 25-42; Thom 2003, 93-6; P. Thom, <strong>Logic</strong> and<br />

Ontology in <strong>the</strong> Syllogistic <strong>of</strong> Robert Kilwardby, Studien und Texte zur Geistesgeschichte des<br />

Mittelalters 92 (Leiden: Brill, 2007), 19-28.

Hooray! Your file is uploaded and ready to be published.

Saved successfully!

Ooh no, something went wrong!