22.06.2013 Views

Handbook of the History of Logic: - Fordham University Faculty

Handbook of the History of Logic: - Fordham University Faculty

Handbook of the History of Logic: - Fordham University Faculty

SHOW MORE
SHOW LESS

Create successful ePaper yourself

Turn your PDF publications into a flip-book with our unique Google optimized e-Paper software.

306 Henrik Lagerlund<br />

matter. If <strong>the</strong> relation is nei<strong>the</strong>r <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong>se, <strong>the</strong>n <strong>the</strong> proposition is in possible or<br />

contingent matter. The way Aquinas outlines <strong>the</strong> modal propositions is very close<br />

to <strong>the</strong> way Robert Kilwardby did it (see <strong>the</strong> discussion in <strong>the</strong> next section). 60<br />

In necessary matter, universal propositions are determinately true, claims Aquinas,<br />

and <strong>the</strong>ir negations are determinately false, since <strong>the</strong>y are in impossible matter.<br />

This holds for past, present as well as future tensed propositions. He <strong>the</strong>n turns to<br />

contingent matter and notes that all universal propositions are false in contingent<br />

matter while particular and indefinite propositions are true for past, present and<br />

future tensed propositions. The reason for this is reviled by <strong>the</strong> square <strong>of</strong> opposition,<br />

since in a contingent proposition both <strong>the</strong> affirmation and negation are true<br />

and that is impossible for universal propositions.<br />

The problem for Aquinas is where to locate singular propositions in this division.<br />

He writes:<br />

In singular future propositions, however, <strong>the</strong>re is a difference. In past<br />

and present singular propositions, one <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> opposites must be determinately<br />

true and <strong>the</strong> o<strong>the</strong>r false in any matter whatsoever, but<br />

in singulars that are about <strong>the</strong> future, it is not necessary that one<br />

be determinately true and <strong>the</strong> o<strong>the</strong>r false. This holds with respect<br />

to contingent matter; with respect to necessary and impossible matter<br />

<strong>the</strong> rule is <strong>the</strong> same as in propositions about <strong>the</strong> present and <strong>the</strong><br />

past. Aristotle has not mentioned contingent matter until now because<br />

those things that take place contingently pertain exclusively to singulars,<br />

whereas those that per se belong or are repugnant are attributed<br />

so singulars according to <strong>the</strong> notions <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong>ir universals. Aristotle is<br />

<strong>the</strong>refore wholly concerned here with this question: whe<strong>the</strong>r in singular<br />

propositions about <strong>the</strong> future in contingent matter it is necessary that<br />

one <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> opposites be determinately true and <strong>the</strong> o<strong>the</strong>r determinately<br />

false. 61<br />

For Aquinas this is <strong>the</strong> problem Aristotle addresses in Chapter 9. The rest <strong>of</strong><br />

Aquinas’ discussion is about whe<strong>the</strong>r singular contingent propositions about <strong>the</strong><br />

future are determinately true or false, or not. He explains <strong>the</strong> problem like this:<br />

If it is necessary that every affirmation or negation about future singulars<br />

is true or false, it is necessary that everyone who affirms or<br />

denies, determinately says what is true and false. From this it follows<br />

that it is necessary that everything be or not be. Therefore, if every<br />

affirmation or negation is determinately true, it is necessary that everything<br />

determinately be or not be. From this he concludes fur<strong>the</strong>r<br />

that all things are <strong>of</strong> necessity. That would exclude <strong>the</strong> three kinds <strong>of</strong><br />

60 See also [Knuuttila, 1981, 208-17; 1993, 129-32].<br />

61 See Thomas Aquinas, Expositio peryermeneias, I.13, n. 6, for <strong>the</strong> Latin, and see [Oesterle,<br />

1962, 103-4], for <strong>the</strong> translation. I have slightly modified it, though.

Hooray! Your file is uploaded and ready to be published.

Saved successfully!

Ooh no, something went wrong!