22.06.2013 Views

Handbook of the History of Logic: - Fordham University Faculty

Handbook of the History of Logic: - Fordham University Faculty

Handbook of the History of Logic: - Fordham University Faculty

SHOW MORE
SHOW LESS

Create successful ePaper yourself

Turn your PDF publications into a flip-book with our unique Google optimized e-Paper software.

678 Russell Wahl<br />

...<strong>the</strong> words “true religion” signify but a single and unique religion,<br />

which is in truth <strong>the</strong> Catholic religion, since that is <strong>the</strong> only true one.<br />

But because each nation and each sect believes that its religion is <strong>the</strong><br />

true one, <strong>the</strong>se words are highly equivocal in people’s mouths, although<br />

by error. And if we read in a historian that a prince was zealous about<br />

<strong>the</strong> true religion, we could not know what was meant unless we knew<br />

this historian’s religion. For if he were a Protestant, it would mean <strong>the</strong><br />

Protestant religion; if he were an Arab Moslem who spoke thus about<br />

his prince, it would mean <strong>the</strong> Moslem religion; and we could judge<br />

that it was <strong>the</strong> Catholic religion only if we knew that <strong>the</strong> historian was<br />

Catholic. (67)<br />

Jean-Claude Pariente has noted that Arnauld used this distinction in his controversy<br />

over <strong>the</strong> refusal <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> Jansenists to sign <strong>the</strong> formulary, and says it anticipates<br />

Keith Donnellan’s distinction between referential and attributive uses <strong>of</strong> descriptions.<br />

17 His description <strong>of</strong> Arnauld’s own account <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> distinction, though, suggests<br />

a closer connection to <strong>the</strong> distinction made between speaker’s reference and<br />

semantic reference, although <strong>the</strong> two are related. 18<br />

Given <strong>the</strong> account <strong>of</strong> a proposition as ei<strong>the</strong>r an affirmation or a denial <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong><br />

relation <strong>of</strong> two terms, it is clear that negation will be seen as part <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> copula.<br />

However, whe<strong>the</strong>r a proposition is universal or particular on this account appears<br />

to be a function <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> subject term. Each idea or term, whe<strong>the</strong>r general or<br />

singular, has an extension as well as a comprehension. One way <strong>of</strong> limiting or<br />

fur<strong>the</strong>r determining that extension was to form a complex idea which has a greater<br />

comprehension and cuts back <strong>the</strong> extension. The o<strong>the</strong>r way was to join to it “only<br />

an indistinct and indeterminate idea <strong>of</strong> a part, as when I say, some triangle ...”<br />

(59). The view here is that <strong>the</strong> quantifiers ‘all’ and ‘some’ are not part <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong><br />

propositional form, but attach to a term as a way <strong>of</strong> determining its extension.<br />

So that ‘all men’ is a complex term in <strong>the</strong> proposition “all men are mortal”, as is<br />

“some men” in “some men are over six feet tall”. While this is <strong>the</strong> <strong>of</strong>ficial view <strong>of</strong><br />

<strong>the</strong> Port-Royal <strong>Logic</strong>, in practice <strong>the</strong>y treat propositions, and not merely subject<br />

terms as universal or particular.<br />

While each idea has an extension, Arnauld and Nicole mark <strong>the</strong> distinction <strong>of</strong><br />

universal and particular propositions as a distinction <strong>of</strong> whe<strong>the</strong>r <strong>the</strong> terms are<br />

“taken” throughout <strong>the</strong>ir entire extensions or only through an “indeterminate<br />

part” <strong>of</strong> that extension. 19 In fact, <strong>the</strong> Port-Royal <strong>Logic</strong> defines <strong>the</strong> distinction<br />

17 [Pariente, 1985, 206]. The reference is to [Donnellan, 1966].<br />

18 Quoting from texts collated by Fa<strong>the</strong>r Quesnel and reprinted in Volume 22 <strong>of</strong> [Arnauld,<br />

1775-1783], Pariente marks <strong>the</strong> distinction between which object is actually determined by <strong>the</strong><br />

property and which object is thought <strong>of</strong> by <strong>the</strong> person who utters <strong>the</strong> description. This way <strong>of</strong><br />

making <strong>the</strong> distinction appears closer to <strong>the</strong> distinction between speaker’s reference and semantic<br />

reference. See [Kripke,1977] and [Donnellan, 1978].<br />

19 “. . . les termes universels peuvent être pris ou selon toute leur étendue, en les joignant aux<br />

signes universels exprimés ou sous-entendus, comme omnis, tout, pour l’affirmation; nullus, nul,<br />

pour la negation, tout homme, nul homme . . . Ou selon une partie indéterminée de leur étendue,<br />

qui est lorsqu’on y joint le mot aliqui, quelque, comme quelque homme, quelque hommes, ou

Hooray! Your file is uploaded and ready to be published.

Saved successfully!

Ooh no, something went wrong!