22.06.2013 Views

Handbook of the History of Logic: - Fordham University Faculty

Handbook of the History of Logic: - Fordham University Faculty

Handbook of the History of Logic: - Fordham University Faculty

SHOW MORE
SHOW LESS

Create successful ePaper yourself

Turn your PDF publications into a flip-book with our unique Google optimized e-Paper software.

434 Catarina Dutilh Novaes<br />

<strong>the</strong> present purposes, it is sufficient to present <strong>the</strong> extension <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> term ‘logic’<br />

in <strong>the</strong> 14 th century — that is, <strong>the</strong> kinds <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong>ories that were treated under <strong>the</strong><br />

heading <strong>of</strong> logic in that period.<br />

As any list <strong>of</strong> 14 th century authors and texts (such as in [Spade, 1996, 329]) will<br />

show, <strong>the</strong> main logical topics treated in that period were: insolubilia (paradoxical<br />

propositions); modal propositions; supposition; <strong>the</strong> analysis (‘pro<strong>of</strong>’) <strong>of</strong> propositions;<br />

obligations; and consequence. One also encounters works bearing <strong>the</strong> title<br />

‘sophismata’ (William Heytesbury, Albert <strong>of</strong> Saxony, Richard Kilvington), but<br />

sophismata are not <strong>the</strong>ories in <strong>the</strong>mselves; ra<strong>the</strong>r, sophismata are logical and/or<br />

philosophical puzzles (cf. [Pironet, 2005]). The apparatus to be used to solve a<br />

given sophisma obviously depends on <strong>the</strong> source <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> problem in question, and<br />

may come from any <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> familiar <strong>the</strong>oretical frameworks most used <strong>the</strong>n (<strong>the</strong>ories<br />

<strong>of</strong> supposition, <strong>the</strong>ories <strong>of</strong> fallacies etc.).<br />

As for <strong>the</strong> first two topics <strong>of</strong> this list, insolubilia and modal propositions (two<br />

<strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> main topics in 14 th century logic), <strong>the</strong>y are treated in detail elsewhere this<br />

volume, so I will not approach <strong>the</strong>m here. We are thus left with <strong>the</strong> o<strong>the</strong>r four<br />

prominent logical genres in <strong>the</strong> 14 th century: supposition, <strong>the</strong> analysis (‘pro<strong>of</strong>’)<br />

<strong>of</strong> propositions, obligationes, and consequence. Indeed, this chapter is composed<br />

<strong>of</strong> three main parts, each <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong>m dedicated to one <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong>se topics – under <strong>the</strong><br />

common heading <strong>of</strong> ‘semantics’, I treat supposition and, briefly, <strong>the</strong> <strong>the</strong>ory <strong>of</strong><br />

pro<strong>of</strong>s <strong>of</strong> propositions. But before I move to <strong>the</strong> study <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong>se three topics,<br />

in a preliminary section I give an overview <strong>of</strong> names, dates and places, so as to<br />

provide <strong>the</strong> reader with some <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> historical background before we proceed to <strong>the</strong><br />

conceptual analysis. The reader may also choose to turn directly to <strong>the</strong> <strong>the</strong>matic<br />

sections, if <strong>the</strong> historical aspects are not her main interest.<br />

1 NAMES, DATES AND PLACES<br />

While it is true that <strong>the</strong>re has been growing interest in 14 th century philosophy<br />

over <strong>the</strong> last decades, and that <strong>the</strong> number <strong>of</strong> publications on this subject has<br />

grown exponentially, we are still nowhere near a complete account <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> historical<br />

and bibliographical events involving <strong>the</strong> authors in question. It is significant,<br />

for example, that even <strong>the</strong> exact date <strong>of</strong> death <strong>of</strong> an author as influential as<br />

John Buridan remains unknown (cf. [Zupko, 2002a, section 1]). It may be a<br />

matter <strong>of</strong> fur<strong>the</strong>r work on <strong>the</strong> extant manuscripts and records, which remain largely<br />

unstudied in libraries, but it may also be that some <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong>se details will never be<br />

revealed for lack <strong>of</strong> extant records.<br />

Be that as it may, and although <strong>the</strong>re is definitely a significant amount <strong>of</strong> work<br />

still to be done on manuscripts and records, scholars have managed to compile an<br />

impressive, albeit incomplete, amount <strong>of</strong> information on <strong>the</strong> philosophers <strong>of</strong> that<br />

period. Here I attempt to present <strong>the</strong> main lines <strong>of</strong> our current state <strong>of</strong> knowledge<br />

on 14 th century philosophers and logicians, especially in view <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> conceptual<br />

analyses to follow. Naturally, several important texts remain without definitive<br />

authorial attribution and are listed as ‘Anonymous’; whenever relevant, such texts

Hooray! Your file is uploaded and ready to be published.

Saved successfully!

Ooh no, something went wrong!