22.06.2013 Views

Handbook of the History of Logic: - Fordham University Faculty

Handbook of the History of Logic: - Fordham University Faculty

Handbook of the History of Logic: - Fordham University Faculty

SHOW MORE
SHOW LESS

You also want an ePaper? Increase the reach of your titles

YUMPU automatically turns print PDFs into web optimized ePapers that Google loves.

682 Russell Wahl<br />

idea in <strong>the</strong> case <strong>of</strong> a universal, and an indeterminate part in <strong>the</strong> case <strong>of</strong> a<br />

particular]. (173-4)<br />

The fifth axiom states that if I assert <strong>the</strong> proposition “No F are G”, and <strong>the</strong> idea G<br />

contains in its comprehension <strong>the</strong> ideas H and K, I am not denying that <strong>the</strong>re are<br />

F ’s that are H or F ’s that are K, but only that <strong>the</strong>re are no F ’s which have both<br />

attributes. The sixth axiom, which corresponds to <strong>the</strong> claim that <strong>the</strong> predicate<br />

term <strong>of</strong> negative propositions is distributed, is argued for somewhat awkwardly by<br />

<strong>the</strong> statement that “if triangle is denied <strong>of</strong> squares, everything that is a triangle<br />

will be denied <strong>of</strong> squares”. “Everything that is a triangle” clearly refers to <strong>the</strong><br />

extension <strong>of</strong> “triangle” here. Presumably in “some figures are not triangles” <strong>the</strong><br />

indeterminate part <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> extension <strong>of</strong> “figures” would not be any <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> species<br />

<strong>of</strong> triangles, and no member <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> indeterminate part would be a member <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong><br />

extension <strong>of</strong> “triangle”. From <strong>the</strong>se axioms, Arnauld and Nicole derive a third<br />

rule, that universal negative propositions can be converted. While <strong>the</strong>y don’t<br />

give a fur<strong>the</strong>r rule about particular negatives, <strong>the</strong>y argue that given <strong>the</strong>se axioms,<br />

<strong>the</strong>y cannot be converted. The argument for <strong>the</strong> third rule is that since, given<br />

<strong>the</strong> sixth and seventh axioms, and <strong>the</strong> fact that in <strong>the</strong> universal propositions <strong>the</strong><br />

entire extension <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> subject is in question, a proposition such as “No F are G”<br />

separates <strong>the</strong> entire extension <strong>of</strong> F from <strong>the</strong> entire extension <strong>of</strong> G, so this separation<br />

will be “mutual and reciprocal.” This is not <strong>the</strong> case with <strong>the</strong> particular negatives,<br />

since in those cases <strong>the</strong> entire extension <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> subject term is not in question, but<br />

only an indeterminate part. So “some person is not a physician” makes an assertion<br />

concerning only an indeterminate part <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> extension <strong>of</strong> “person” while “some<br />

physician is not a person” makes a claim concerning its entire extension.<br />

In a brief section on <strong>the</strong> square <strong>of</strong> opposition <strong>the</strong> Port-Royal <strong>Logic</strong> gives <strong>the</strong> traditional<br />

relations <strong>of</strong> contradictories, subcontraries, contraries and subaltern (117).<br />

Unfortunately, <strong>the</strong>re is no discussion <strong>of</strong> existential presupposition. It is clear that<br />

Arnauld and Nicole hold that <strong>the</strong> affirmative propositions carry existential presupposition,<br />

but <strong>the</strong>y are not explicit with respect to negative propositions, which<br />

were held by many mediaeval logicians not to have any existential presupposition,<br />

thus preserving all <strong>the</strong> relations <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> square. 24 On this view <strong>the</strong> immediate<br />

inference <strong>of</strong> obversion doesn’t hold, and <strong>the</strong>re is no mention <strong>of</strong> this inference in<br />

<strong>the</strong> Port-Royal <strong>Logic</strong>. Jean-Claude Pariente has argued that since ideas which<br />

are species <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> general ideas are counted in <strong>the</strong> extension <strong>of</strong> terms, <strong>the</strong>re is a<br />

sense in which all terms, even those which do not have any existing particulars in<br />

<strong>the</strong>ir extensions, do have things in <strong>the</strong>ir extension, and he uses this to justify a<br />

claim <strong>of</strong> existential presupposition for all terms. 25 As far as I can tell, <strong>the</strong> text <strong>of</strong><br />

<strong>the</strong> <strong>Logic</strong> does not really lend support to this interpretation. There is, though, a<br />

24 See [Moody, 1953, 50–51], for a discussion <strong>of</strong> Buriden on this point, and Freddoso, “Ockham’s<br />

Theory <strong>of</strong> Truth Conditions”, [Freddoso and Schurrman, 1980, 18], for a discussion <strong>of</strong> Ockham.<br />

25 See [Pariente, 1985, 246]: “These observations explain at least in part <strong>the</strong> indifference <strong>of</strong> Port-<br />

Royal to problems posed for logic by empty terms. When <strong>the</strong> logic is presented as a calculus<br />

applying to ideas, and more precisely to relations between extensions <strong>of</strong> ideas, <strong>the</strong> possibility or<br />

impossibility <strong>of</strong> applying <strong>the</strong>se ideas to concrete realities has no effect on <strong>the</strong> calculus itself.”

Hooray! Your file is uploaded and ready to be published.

Saved successfully!

Ooh no, something went wrong!