22.06.2013 Views

Handbook of the History of Logic: - Fordham University Faculty

Handbook of the History of Logic: - Fordham University Faculty

Handbook of the History of Logic: - Fordham University Faculty

SHOW MORE
SHOW LESS

You also want an ePaper? Increase the reach of your titles

YUMPU automatically turns print PDFs into web optimized ePapers that Google loves.

Developments in <strong>the</strong> Fifteenth and Sixteenth Centuries 637<br />

or politics?” 135 This was not a new question. Aristotle’s Rhetoric as well as his<br />

Poetics had come to be regarded by <strong>the</strong> late Greek commentators <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> School <strong>of</strong><br />

Alexandria as part <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> Organon, that is, as part <strong>of</strong> logic in a wide sense, and <strong>the</strong><br />

Arabs followed this established tradition. 136 Albert <strong>the</strong> Great, Aquinas, and Simon<br />

<strong>of</strong> Faversham, among o<strong>the</strong>rs, followed <strong>the</strong> Arabs, at least in principle. If we look<br />

at Aquinas’s analysis <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> parts <strong>of</strong> logic in his Posterior Analytics commentary,<br />

we find that demonstrative syllogisms produce certainty, while dialectic deals with<br />

arguments on <strong>the</strong> basis <strong>of</strong> probable premisses that produce opinion or belief, and<br />

rhetoric deals with arguments whose premisses produce suspicio, an inclination to<br />

accept one position ra<strong>the</strong>r than its opposite. 137 In <strong>the</strong> sixteenth century, <strong>the</strong> most<br />

conspicuous defender <strong>of</strong> this tradition was Zabarella, who devoted a large part<br />

<strong>of</strong> his work De natura logicae to arguing that rhetoric and poetics were genuine<br />

parts <strong>of</strong> logic. 138 None <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong>se claims seem to have had any practical impact. One<br />

reason for this, at least during <strong>the</strong> medieval period, was <strong>the</strong> relative inaccessability<br />

<strong>of</strong> Aristotle’s Rhetoric and Poetics, but during <strong>the</strong> sixteenth century, when <strong>the</strong>se<br />

works were readily available, 139 <strong>the</strong> consensus seemed to be that while rhetoric<br />

should be taught in tandem with dialectic, it should none<strong>the</strong>less be regarded as a<br />

separate discipline.<br />

The most important issue is how <strong>the</strong> five parts <strong>of</strong> rhetoric, namely inventio,<br />

dispositio, or <strong>the</strong> structuring and arrangement <strong>of</strong> material, elocutio, memoria and<br />

pronuntiatio, were to be handled. For Agricola and Ramus, dispositio was interchangeable<br />

with judgement, and both inventio and dispositio were to be handled<br />

by <strong>the</strong> logician. This arrangement left matters <strong>of</strong> eloquence to <strong>the</strong> rhetorician,<br />

and anything to do with <strong>the</strong> Topics, with argumentation, or with <strong>the</strong> ordering <strong>of</strong><br />

discourse to <strong>the</strong> logician. With respect to inventio, Agricola insisted that <strong>the</strong> Topics<br />

were to be confined to dialectic, and that rhetorical Topics, which had covered<br />

material <strong>of</strong> a more particular kind, were to be reduced to dialectical Topics. 140 In<br />

135 Herbert S. Matsen, “Student “Arts” Disputations at Bologna around 1500”, Renaissance<br />

Quarterly 47 (1994), p. 545. Rhetoric came after logic in order <strong>of</strong> importance as a disputation<br />

topic, op.cit., p. 543 and p. 545.<br />

136 Black, Deborah L. <strong>Logic</strong> and Aristotle’s ‘Rhetoric’ and ‘Poetics’ in Medieval Arabic Philosophy.<br />

Leiden etc.: E.J. Brill, 1990, pp. 17–18; Marmo, Costantino. ‘Suspicio: AKeyWordto<strong>the</strong><br />

Significance <strong>of</strong> Aristotle’s Rhetoric in Thirteenth Century Scholasticism.’ Cahiers de l’institut<br />

du moyen-âge grec et latin 60 (1990), 145–198.<br />

137 Thomas Aquinas, In Aristotelis libros Peri Hermenias et Posteriorum Analyticorum Expositio<br />

(Turin: Marietti, 1964), Prooemium §6, pp. 147–148. He writes, p. 148: “Per huiusmodi<br />

enim processum, quandoque quidem, etsi non fiat scientia, fit tamen fides vel opinio propter<br />

probabilitatem propositionum, ex quibus proceditur: quia ratio totaliter declinat in unam partem<br />

contradictionis, licet cum formidine alterius, et ad hoc ordinatur Topica sive Dialectica. Namsyllogismus<br />

dialecticus ex probabilibus est, de quo agit Aristoteles in libro Topicorum. Quandoque<br />

vero, non fit complete fides vel opinio, sed suspicio quaedam, quia non totaliter declinatur ad<br />

unam partem contradictionis, licet magis inclinetur in hanc quam in illam. Et ad hoc ordinatur<br />

Rhetorica.”<br />

138 Zabarella, De natura logicae in Opera omnia, cols. 71–100.<br />

139 See Brian Vickers, “Rhetoric and Poetics” in The Cambridge <strong>History</strong> <strong>of</strong> Renaissance Philosophy,<br />

p. 718 for details <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> reception <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> Poetics in <strong>the</strong> sixteenth century, and p. 721<br />

for <strong>the</strong> reception <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> Rhetoric.<br />

140 Agricola, De Inventione Dialectica, pp. 313–319. Boethius had discussed <strong>the</strong> relationship

Hooray! Your file is uploaded and ready to be published.

Saved successfully!

Ooh no, something went wrong!