22.06.2013 Views

Handbook of the History of Logic: - Fordham University Faculty

Handbook of the History of Logic: - Fordham University Faculty

Handbook of the History of Logic: - Fordham University Faculty

SHOW MORE
SHOW LESS

Create successful ePaper yourself

Turn your PDF publications into a flip-book with our unique Google optimized e-Paper software.

The Development <strong>of</strong> Supposition Theory in <strong>the</strong> Later 12 th through 14 th Centuries 261<br />

Ockham and Buridan agree on this definition. 120 Burley gives <strong>the</strong> same account<br />

but omits <strong>the</strong> ascent condition. 121 I assume that this is an oversight — if <strong>the</strong><br />

ascent condition were omitted <strong>the</strong>n <strong>the</strong> definition would not cohere with many<br />

paradigm cases. For example, ‘donkey’ in ‘Every donkey is running’ would be<br />

determinate because one can descend to a disjunction. The notion <strong>of</strong> determinate<br />

supposition was quite stable from author to author.<br />

8.9.2 Distributive Supposition122 Our definition <strong>of</strong> distributive supposition has been:<br />

A term F has distributive supposition in a proposition P if and only if<br />

[Descent]: you may descend under F to a conjunction <strong>of</strong><br />

propositional instances <strong>of</strong> all <strong>the</strong> F s, and<br />

[Ascent]: from any one instance you may not ascend back to<br />

<strong>the</strong> original proposition P .<br />

This is essentially Ockham’s definition. 123 Buridan and o<strong>the</strong>rs omit <strong>the</strong> condition<br />

that prohibits ascent from an instance. 124 I am not certain how important this is.<br />

That is because <strong>the</strong> prohibition <strong>of</strong> ascent may be redundant. For <strong>the</strong>re to be a case<br />

in which one can descend to a conjunction, and <strong>the</strong>n ascend from any instance,<br />

one would need a proposition and a common term in it such that <strong>the</strong> proposition<br />

is logically equivalent to any <strong>of</strong> its descended forms. I suspect that it is impossible<br />

120 Albert <strong>of</strong> Saxony (SL II.4) gives an equivalent account: “Determinate supposition is <strong>the</strong><br />

use <strong>of</strong> a general term for each <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> things it signifies by its imposition, or which it signifies<br />

naturally (if it is a mental term), in such manner that a descent to its singulars can be effected<br />

by a disjunctive proposition. In this sentence, ‘A man runs’, <strong>the</strong> term ‘man’ has determinate<br />

supposition, because <strong>the</strong> term ‘man’ in this sentence stands, disjunctively, for everything which<br />

it signifies by its imposition. For it is sufficient, for <strong>the</strong> truth <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> proposition ‘A man runs’,<br />

that this disjunctive proposition be true: ‘This man runs, or that man runs’, and so on for all<br />

singulars.” Since any disjunct entails <strong>the</strong> disjunction, this last sentence gives <strong>the</strong> ascent condition.<br />

Paul <strong>of</strong> Venice LM 3.8 (89) gives a vaguer account that is <strong>the</strong> same if one takes for granted that<br />

he is discussing disjunctions: “Determinate supposition is <strong>the</strong> meaning <strong>of</strong> a term in a proposition<br />

beneath which one can infer all <strong>of</strong> its referents and conversely on <strong>the</strong> condition <strong>of</strong> a proper<br />

middle.”<br />

121 Paul <strong>of</strong> Venice LP 2.4 (149) gives <strong>the</strong> same account as Burley.<br />

122 Buridan’s account omits <strong>the</strong> non-ascent condition. Ockham includes additional provisions<br />

for immobile distribution. Burley does not define distributive supposition; instead he defines two<br />

kinds <strong>of</strong> distributive supposition. This is discussed below.<br />

123 See note 101<br />

124 See note 101 for Buridan’s view. O<strong>the</strong>r authors than Buridan gave equivalent definitions.<br />

Albert <strong>of</strong> Saxony SL II.4 states: “Confused and distributive supposition is <strong>the</strong> interpretation <strong>of</strong><br />

a spoken or written term, in conjunctive manner, for each thing which it is instituted to signify;<br />

or it is <strong>the</strong> interpretation <strong>of</strong> a mental term for each thing which it signifies naturally—-such that<br />

a descent to <strong>the</strong> singulars, for which it stands, can be made in conjunctive manner, by reason <strong>of</strong><br />

that supposition.” This account was also given by at least two anonymous early authors (in [De<br />

Rijk, 1967]): [UD] “Confused and distributive is when <strong>of</strong> necessity a descent is made to every<br />

inferior.” and [CSN] “Confused and distributive supposition is when a common term supposits<br />

for its inferiors and it is possible to make a descent under it to any appellated content under <strong>the</strong><br />

distributive term.”.

Hooray! Your file is uploaded and ready to be published.

Saved successfully!

Ooh no, something went wrong!