22.06.2013 Views

Handbook of the History of Logic: - Fordham University Faculty

Handbook of the History of Logic: - Fordham University Faculty

Handbook of the History of Logic: - Fordham University Faculty

SHOW MORE
SHOW LESS

You also want an ePaper? Increase the reach of your titles

YUMPU automatically turns print PDFs into web optimized ePapers that Google loves.

The Assimilation <strong>of</strong> Aristotelian and Arabic <strong>Logic</strong> up to <strong>the</strong> Later Thirteenth Century 311<br />

4.4 The Topics<br />

Before <strong>the</strong> thirteenth century <strong>the</strong> discussion <strong>of</strong> Aristotle’s Topics was completely<br />

dominated by Boethius’ De differentiis topicis, which is not really a commentary<br />

<strong>of</strong> Aristotle’s work, but a mix <strong>of</strong> Aristotle and Cicero. The first extant Latin<br />

commentary on Aristotle’s Topics is from c. 1235. Naturally, Boethius remained<br />

influential well into <strong>the</strong> thirteenth century; although <strong>the</strong>y gradually stopped commenting<br />

on his work.<br />

In <strong>the</strong> first chapter <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> first book <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> Topics, Aristotle writes (100a10-20):<br />

The goal <strong>of</strong> this study is to find a method with which we shall be able to<br />

construct deductions (syllogisms) from acceptable premises concerning<br />

any problem that is proposed and – when submitted to arguments<br />

ourselves – will not say anything inconsistent.<br />

This is <strong>the</strong> method <strong>of</strong> dialectics. It is an argumentative method in dialogue form<br />

between a questioner and an answerer. These two first agree upon a problem (a<br />

question), which usually is a proposition expressing a well accepted opinion. Next<br />

<strong>the</strong> questioner puts forward questions to <strong>the</strong> answerer, which he/she answers with<br />

‘Yes’ or ‘No’, that is, he/she accepts <strong>the</strong> propositions proposed or denies <strong>the</strong>m.<br />

The accepted question or proposition <strong>the</strong>n becomes premises in <strong>the</strong> argument. The<br />

purpose <strong>of</strong> this exercise is to examine <strong>the</strong> agreed upon problem and show that it<br />

leads to inconsistencies or at least to opinions not acceptable to <strong>the</strong> answerer.<br />

Aristotle never tells <strong>the</strong> reader what a topic (topos) is, but he gives examples<br />

in Books II-VII <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> Topics, but as many commentators have observed it is not<br />

always helpful to have lots <strong>of</strong> examples. The problem has been to understand<br />

what <strong>the</strong>y are examples <strong>of</strong>. In <strong>the</strong> Rhetorics, Aristotle gives us some help. There<br />

he notes that <strong>the</strong> topoi are “that under which many arguments fall” (1403a17-<br />

8). This suggests that <strong>the</strong> topoi are classifications <strong>of</strong> arguments, that is, <strong>the</strong>y are<br />

argumentative forms.<br />

The Latin name for a topic is a locus. Boethius defines a locus as: “that<br />

by which <strong>the</strong> argument is settled, or that by which from a proposed question<br />

<strong>the</strong> argument is drawn out.” 72 According to Boethius, it is hence about finding<br />

arguments from particular questions (or premises) to conclusions, which means<br />

that it is by finding <strong>the</strong> locus or <strong>the</strong> middle term that we can find <strong>the</strong> argument<br />

that gets us from question to conclusion.<br />

Strictly speaking a question is <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> form ‘Ei<strong>the</strong>r A is B or A is not-B’, and<br />

<strong>the</strong> problem is which disjunct should be accepted? The question is answered by<br />

an argument, and Boethius understands it as being syllogistically structured, but<br />

what he presents are not valid syllogisms. In syllogistics, <strong>the</strong> problem is, once<br />

one knows <strong>the</strong> system, finding <strong>the</strong> middle term, and <strong>the</strong> <strong>the</strong>ory <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> topics<br />

systematises <strong>the</strong> process <strong>of</strong> finding <strong>the</strong> middle term. There is no standard way<br />

<strong>of</strong> doing this though, since <strong>the</strong>y will always depend on <strong>the</strong> particular argument.<br />

72Boethius, De differentiis topicis in [Stump, 1978, 30]. The translation is here slightly modified.

Hooray! Your file is uploaded and ready to be published.

Saved successfully!

Ooh no, something went wrong!