22.06.2013 Views

Handbook of the History of Logic: - Fordham University Faculty

Handbook of the History of Logic: - Fordham University Faculty

Handbook of the History of Logic: - Fordham University Faculty

SHOW MORE
SHOW LESS

Create successful ePaper yourself

Turn your PDF publications into a flip-book with our unique Google optimized e-Paper software.

592 Mikko Yrjönsuuri<br />

else as well. The first part <strong>of</strong> this pro<strong>of</strong> is relatively understandable, and we can<br />

still use ‘a’ as a name for <strong>the</strong> sentence at issue (although it must now be taken as<br />

a name for an arbitrary sentence satisfying <strong>the</strong> criterion <strong>of</strong> self-reference, or any<br />

sentence for which <strong>the</strong> first premise (1) is true). 20<br />

Pro<strong>of</strong>.<br />

(1) ‘a’ signifies only that ‘a’ is not true Assumed<br />

(2) ‘a’ is not true Assumed<br />

(3) It is not wholly as ‘a’ signifies (2), (Def. <strong>of</strong> truth)<br />

(4) It is not <strong>the</strong> case that ‘a’ is not true (1), (3), (T1.2)<br />

(5) ‘a’ is true (4)<br />

(6) ‘a’ signifies itself to be true (1), (2)–(5), (P2)<br />

Most steps <strong>of</strong> this argument seem clear enough. In essence, (3) expresses what<br />

it is for ‘a’ not to be true. 21 Then at step (4), ‘<strong>the</strong> case that ‘a’ is not true’ is<br />

substituted for ‘wholly as ‘a’ signifies’ since that is all that ‘a’ signifies according to<br />

(1). Then at step (5) <strong>the</strong> double negation is eliminated. At step (6), Bradwardine<br />

applies his principle (P2), which is doing <strong>the</strong> crucial work.<br />

A reader may wonder about <strong>the</strong> line (2) and <strong>the</strong> application <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> principle<br />

(P2). Is line (2) assumed for <strong>the</strong> sake <strong>of</strong> conditional pro<strong>of</strong>? The lines (2)–(5)<br />

would <strong>the</strong>n infer “a’ is true’ from “a’ is not true’. The consequence would <strong>the</strong>n<br />

be used at (6). This interpretation seems a good suggestion, especially in view <strong>of</strong><br />

applying <strong>the</strong> principle (P2) on (1) to achieve (6). However, again it seems that it<br />

is (P2)* that is needed, since line (2) appears to be what ‘a’ signifies and not <strong>the</strong><br />

examined sentence ‘a’ itself. 22 The reasoning seems to run from ‘a’ :¬T ‘a’ (cf.<br />

(1)), proving (on steps (2)–(5)) <strong>the</strong> consequence ¬T ‘a’ → T ‘a’ and using it with<br />

<strong>the</strong> principle (P2)* to achieve ‘a’ :T ‘a’.<br />

The second part <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> pro<strong>of</strong> is more difficult. What if <strong>the</strong> examined sentence<br />

means something else as well? Bradwardine proceeds as follows. Let that o<strong>the</strong>r<br />

signification be ‘B is C’, and run <strong>the</strong> reasoning similarly. Now it is as follows: 23<br />

20 In Stephen Read’s translation, <strong>the</strong> text runs as follows: “Let A be a proposition signifying<br />

itself not to be true, whe<strong>the</strong>r signifying anything else or not. If not, <strong>the</strong>n it follows from <strong>the</strong><br />

assumption that A is not true, by definition (D1), that it is not wholly as is signified by A, and<br />

by A is signified only that A is not true (we supposed), so by <strong>the</strong>sis (T1.2) it follows that it is<br />

not <strong>the</strong> case that A is not true, that is, that A is true, whence by postulate (P2) A signifies itself<br />

to be true.” [Bradwardine, internet, 45]. The pro<strong>of</strong> has been analyzed in [Spade, 1981, 120–125;<br />

Read, 2002, 211–212], but my analysis differs slightly from both. See also [Read, forthcoming,<br />

8–10].<br />

21 Bradwardine refers to his definition D1 (see footnote 19).<br />

22 There seems to be no sufficient reason for assimilating ‘a’ with“a’ is false’, since Bradwardine<br />

quite explicitly presents <strong>the</strong> reasoning as something that applies to any sentence ‘a’ signifying<br />

its own falsity, and “a’ is false’ is certainly only one such.<br />

23 The text continues from footnote 19: “If, on <strong>the</strong> o<strong>the</strong>r hand, A signifies more than that it

Hooray! Your file is uploaded and ready to be published.

Saved successfully!

Ooh no, something went wrong!