22.06.2013 Views

Handbook of the History of Logic: - Fordham University Faculty

Handbook of the History of Logic: - Fordham University Faculty

Handbook of the History of Logic: - Fordham University Faculty

SHOW MORE
SHOW LESS

Create successful ePaper yourself

Turn your PDF publications into a flip-book with our unique Google optimized e-Paper software.

638 E. Jennifer Ashworth<br />

<strong>the</strong> hands <strong>of</strong> Philip Melanchthon <strong>the</strong>re was no real reduction, but instead a listing<br />

<strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> so-called personal Topics, such as nation, age, education and sex, within<br />

dialectic itself. 141 With respect to dispositio, Agricola discussed <strong>the</strong> problem <strong>of</strong><br />

presenting and organizing complete arguments and narrations, whe<strong>the</strong>r written or<br />

spoken, at great length. In Melanchthon we find <strong>the</strong> same interest in dispositio. A<br />

few remarks on order in <strong>the</strong> Compendiaria Dialectices Ratio grew into a full section<br />

on logical method as a way <strong>of</strong> ordering discourse in <strong>the</strong> Erotemata Dialectices. 142<br />

In turn we find method discussed in <strong>the</strong> second part <strong>of</strong> Ramus’s Dialectica, but<br />

as we can see from his references to Agricola and Melanchthon, it is a mistake to<br />

think that this was Ramus’s innovation. Sections on method became a standard<br />

component <strong>of</strong> logic textbooks, and particularly after <strong>the</strong> publication <strong>of</strong> Zabarella’s<br />

Opera logica, it became customary to add remarks on scientific method as well, in<br />

a mixture <strong>of</strong> subject-matters that was not always happy. 143<br />

To conclude, if we mean by <strong>the</strong> rhetoricizing <strong>of</strong> logic that material from <strong>the</strong><br />

rhetoricians came to be included in logic texts, this is certainly <strong>the</strong> case. How far<br />

<strong>the</strong> material absorbed included informal persuasive devices is ano<strong>the</strong>r matter.<br />

4 INFORMAL ARGUMENTATION<br />

Whe<strong>the</strong>r or not sixteenth-century logic leaves room for <strong>the</strong> notion <strong>of</strong> informal<br />

arguments depends on how ‘formal’ and ‘informal’ are to be defined. The first<br />

thing we need to understand is that logic was never formal in <strong>the</strong> modern sense.<br />

There was no notion <strong>of</strong> an uninterpreted system with its own set <strong>of</strong> properties,<br />

nor was <strong>the</strong>re any notion <strong>of</strong> a formal interpretation such that, for instance, any<br />

proposition just says T or F. While letters such as ‘a’ and ‘b’ could be used to<br />

stand for propositions, and rules could be described in neutral language, <strong>the</strong> basic<br />

assumption was always that logic served <strong>the</strong> purpose <strong>of</strong> finding and expressing<br />

truths. That being said, one might make a distinction between formal and informal<br />

arguments in terms <strong>of</strong> deductive validity, so that an informal argument is one<br />

that is acceptable but not deductively valid. This still leaves various possibilities<br />

open, with respect to both categories. In <strong>the</strong> case <strong>of</strong> valid deductive arguments,<br />

we need a fur<strong>the</strong>r distinction between formal and non-formal arguments. Some<br />

arguments are such that <strong>the</strong>ir conclusion is true whenever <strong>the</strong> premisses are true,<br />

no matter what non-logical terms are substituted. O<strong>the</strong>r arguments are such<br />

that <strong>the</strong>ir conclusion is true whenever <strong>the</strong> premisses are true just because <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong><br />

between rhetorical and dialectical Topics: see Stump, Boethius’s De topicis differentiis, pp.<br />

79–95.<br />

141 Melanchthon, Compendiaria Dialectices Ratio, cols. 751–755; Erotemata Dialectices, cols.<br />

659–662.<br />

142 Melanchthon, Compendiaria Dialectices Ratio, cols. 724–726; Erotemata Dialectices, cols.<br />

573–578.<br />

143 For more on discussions <strong>of</strong> method, see Cesare Vasoli, “The Renaissance concept <strong>of</strong> philosophy”<br />

in The Cambridge <strong>History</strong> <strong>of</strong> Renaissance Philosophy, pp. 71–72; Jardine, “Humanistic<br />

logic”, pp. 191–192; Ashworth, introduction to Sanderson, <strong>Logic</strong>ae Artis Compendium, pp.<br />

XLVIII–L.

Hooray! Your file is uploaded and ready to be published.

Saved successfully!

Ooh no, something went wrong!