22.06.2013 Views

Handbook of the History of Logic: - Fordham University Faculty

Handbook of the History of Logic: - Fordham University Faculty

Handbook of the History of Logic: - Fordham University Faculty

SHOW MORE
SHOW LESS

Create successful ePaper yourself

Turn your PDF publications into a flip-book with our unique Google optimized e-Paper software.

564 Simo Knuuttila<br />

means, consenting to <strong>the</strong> antecedent (goal) implies consenting to <strong>the</strong> consequent<br />

(a means). 232<br />

Some twelfth-century authors realized that even though willing an end effectively<br />

implies that a necessary means to it is also willed, a rule (W), analogical<br />

to (5) cannot be applied without restriction to efficient will in <strong>the</strong> form that if<br />

Socrates wills that p and he knows that <strong>the</strong>re is a valid consequence from p to q,<br />

he also wills that q. The principle holds about <strong>the</strong> end-means relationship, but <strong>the</strong><br />

necessary means are not <strong>the</strong> only consequents <strong>of</strong> what is willed. Peter <strong>of</strong> Poitiers<br />

formulated a counter-example as follows: if S repents <strong>of</strong> a sin, S is guilty <strong>of</strong> a sin,<br />

and S wills to repent <strong>of</strong> a sin, but S does not will to be guilty <strong>of</strong> a sin. 233 Stephen<br />

Langton’s counter-example was <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> same type: if a man visits his sick fa<strong>the</strong>r,<br />

<strong>the</strong> fa<strong>the</strong>r is sick. This man wills to visit his sick fa<strong>the</strong>r, but it does not follow<br />

that he wills <strong>the</strong> fa<strong>the</strong>r to be sick. 234<br />

When it was realized that one cannot apply (W) to effective will without qualification,<br />

medieval thinkers took an interest in finding cases in which a rational<br />

agent does not will <strong>the</strong> consequent <strong>of</strong> what he or she wills. The twelfth-century<br />

examples just mentioned specify <strong>the</strong> case in which to will something in certain circumstances<br />

implies that those circumstances prevail, although this is something<br />

which <strong>the</strong> agent does not will. This exception to (W) was thought philosophically<br />

interesting and was also used in later medieval deontic logic. Contrary to<br />

what Abelard thought, it was realized that (4) and (5) cannot be applied without<br />

qualification to <strong>the</strong> notions <strong>of</strong> obligation and permission. The reasons were similar<br />

to those which demanded <strong>the</strong> qualification <strong>of</strong> (W). Ano<strong>the</strong>r relevant but more<br />

problematic idea was that a separately unwanted side-effect <strong>of</strong> what is willed is<br />

willed more indirectly than a separately unwanted means to an end. This line <strong>of</strong><br />

thought forms <strong>the</strong> background to Thomas Aquinas’s distinctions between directly<br />

and indirectly willed things. 235<br />

One can follow <strong>the</strong> discussion <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> question <strong>of</strong> how (W) should be qualified<br />

with respect to will by tracing <strong>the</strong> comments on <strong>the</strong> example <strong>of</strong> a man who ‘wills to<br />

be in <strong>the</strong> mud and have 100 marks’ (in luto esse cum 100 marchis). This example<br />

was considered ambiguous, and it was possible to interpret it (i) as a case <strong>of</strong> willing<br />

reluctantly to become dirty as a means <strong>of</strong> receiving 100 marks, (ii) as a case <strong>of</strong><br />

willing to become dirty as a side-effect or (iii) willing something in a situation in<br />

which one would become dirty in any case. The third alternative was particularly<br />

relevant to later discussions <strong>of</strong> conditional obligations.<br />

The most extensive fourteenth-century discussion <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> logical properties <strong>of</strong><br />

deontic concepts is to be found in <strong>the</strong> first question <strong>of</strong> Roger Roseth’s Lecture on<br />

232Ethics 8.21-10.2; 14.14-19; 16.11-18.<br />

233Sententiae IV.16 in Patrologia latina, ed. J.P. Migne, 211, 1199.<br />

234Quaestiones <strong>the</strong>ologiae, quoted in R. Quinto, ‘Die Quaestiones des Stephan Langton über<br />

die Gottesfurcht’, Cahiers de l’Institut du Moyen-Âge Grec et Latin, Université de Copenhague<br />

62 (1992), 77-165, at 129-130.<br />

235See, e.g., Summa <strong>the</strong>ologiae II.2.64.7-8; De malo 2.1. See also Knuuttila 2006, 205-18.

Hooray! Your file is uploaded and ready to be published.

Saved successfully!

Ooh no, something went wrong!