22.06.2013 Views

Handbook of the History of Logic: - Fordham University Faculty

Handbook of the History of Logic: - Fordham University Faculty

Handbook of the History of Logic: - Fordham University Faculty

SHOW MORE
SHOW LESS

Create successful ePaper yourself

Turn your PDF publications into a flip-book with our unique Google optimized e-Paper software.

380 Ria van der Lecq<br />

that are real and not caused by <strong>the</strong> intellect. Predicates <strong>of</strong> second intentions<br />

(genus, species, universal) are <strong>the</strong> object <strong>of</strong> study <strong>of</strong> logicians, not, however, in<br />

<strong>the</strong>ir role <strong>of</strong> real habits, but in <strong>the</strong>ir function <strong>of</strong> concept and likeness.<br />

On <strong>the</strong> level <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> second and third mental operations (composition and reasoning)<br />

it is less obvious how <strong>the</strong> connection between thought and reality can be<br />

preserved, since syllogisms and propositions etc. seem to be mental constructions.<br />

Never<strong>the</strong>less, Radulphus argues that all second intentions have a relation to <strong>the</strong><br />

real world, because ultimately “all logical operations have to be interpreted and<br />

verified <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> things.” 169 In ano<strong>the</strong>r version <strong>of</strong> his <strong>the</strong>ory, however, Radulphus<br />

admits that second intentions <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> second and third kind are entirely caused by<br />

<strong>the</strong> intellect. Thus, <strong>the</strong>se second intentions seem to be less real than <strong>the</strong> second<br />

intentions belonging to <strong>the</strong> level <strong>of</strong> apprehension. Since logic is mainly about this<br />

kind <strong>of</strong> intentions, it is called a rational science ra<strong>the</strong>r than a real science. 170<br />

Radulphus’ opinions were criticized and modified by Hervaeus Natalis and Peter<br />

Aureol, but first we will turn our attention to his contemporary Duns Scotus.<br />

Duns Scotus on intentional being<br />

Duns Scotus (1266–1308) is <strong>the</strong> first to extend <strong>the</strong> realm <strong>of</strong> being to intentional<br />

being (esse intentionale, esse diminutum). Because even something that does not<br />

exist can be <strong>the</strong> object <strong>of</strong> our cognition, he concludes that that object cannot<br />

be a real extra-mental entity. Therefore, it is a concept or intention, not to be<br />

confused with <strong>the</strong> object <strong>of</strong> intention in reality (ratio formalis in re), upon which<br />

it is founded when <strong>the</strong> object exists.<br />

In <strong>the</strong> cognitive process Duns Scotus distinguishes between two acts: <strong>the</strong> sensitive<br />

act <strong>of</strong> perceiving <strong>the</strong> extra-mental object, and <strong>the</strong> intellective act <strong>of</strong> representing<br />

it. This intellective act produces an intelligible species. By producing<br />

an intelligible species one is able to abstract from <strong>the</strong> particular circumstances<br />

in which <strong>the</strong> perception occurs. The species, however, is not <strong>the</strong> object <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong><br />

intellect. It is merely an instrument, a device we need in <strong>the</strong> cognitive process. It<br />

cannot be <strong>the</strong> object <strong>of</strong> knowledge, because it is private to one’s individual intellect,<br />

whereas an object <strong>of</strong> knowledge is common to several people. 171 The primary<br />

object <strong>of</strong> knowledge is <strong>the</strong> intention, or in Scotus’ words: intelligible being (esse<br />

intelligibele). The species has real being (existence) as a quality in <strong>the</strong> intellect,<br />

but <strong>the</strong> intelligible being has only diminished or obiective being, i.e. as an object<br />

<strong>of</strong> knowledge. It is not only <strong>the</strong> object <strong>of</strong> a human intellect, but also <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> divine<br />

intellect. 172 This guarantees <strong>the</strong> reliability <strong>of</strong> our intellectual knowledge <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong><br />

world. In producing <strong>the</strong> intelligible species, <strong>the</strong> human intellect has access to <strong>the</strong><br />

realm <strong>of</strong> intelligible being. In <strong>the</strong> species <strong>the</strong> intellect sees <strong>the</strong> object with intelligi-<br />

169 Knudsen [1982, p. 489].<br />

170 paragraph 58-59, [ed. Pinborg, p. 147].<br />

171 Perler [2001, p. 208].<br />

172 Opus Oxoniense, I dist. III, q. iv. For <strong>the</strong> complex problem <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> ontological status <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong><br />

intelligible being, see Perler [2002, pp. 217–230].

Hooray! Your file is uploaded and ready to be published.

Saved successfully!

Ooh no, something went wrong!