22.06.2013 Views

Handbook of the History of Logic: - Fordham University Faculty

Handbook of the History of Logic: - Fordham University Faculty

Handbook of the History of Logic: - Fordham University Faculty

SHOW MORE
SHOW LESS

You also want an ePaper? Increase the reach of your titles

YUMPU automatically turns print PDFs into web optimized ePapers that Google loves.

Medieval Modal Theories and Modal <strong>Logic</strong> 547<br />

As distinct from his forerunners, Campsall comments separately on Aristotelian<br />

modal syllogisms with premises in <strong>the</strong> compound and divided senses. Uniform<br />

necessity syllogisms are valid on both readings. Syllogisms in <strong>the</strong> compound sense<br />

are reduced to <strong>the</strong> principle<br />

(20) If <strong>the</strong> premises are necessary, <strong>the</strong> consequent is necessary.<br />

Syllogisms in <strong>the</strong> divided sense are valid because <strong>the</strong>y are regulated by <strong>the</strong> same<br />

principles as <strong>the</strong> assertoric syllogisms, i.e., dici de omni et nullo. 152 Mixed necessityassertoric<br />

moods are valid in <strong>the</strong> compound sense on <strong>the</strong> basis <strong>of</strong> (20), when <strong>the</strong><br />

assertoric premise (de inesse proposition) is <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> de inesse simpliciter type, i.e.,<br />

necessarily true. These consequences are not syllogistic, however, and <strong>the</strong> same<br />

holds <strong>of</strong> mixed assertoric-necessity moods with a necessary conclusion. Mixed<br />

necessity-assertoric syllogisms in <strong>the</strong> divided sense are valid when <strong>the</strong> assertoric<br />

premise is de inesse simpliciter or ut nunc primo modo, i.e., a proposition which<br />

express a necessary relation between actual things. Propositions de inesse secundo<br />

modo express accidental relations and assertoric minor premises <strong>of</strong> this kind do<br />

not make valid syllogisms. Campsall describes <strong>the</strong> validity <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> perfect necessityassertoric<br />

syllogisms by referring, like Kilwardby, to <strong>the</strong> principle that <strong>the</strong> whole<br />

syllogism is implicitly included in <strong>the</strong> first premise. The middle term is said to<br />

be sufficiently <strong>the</strong> same in both premises only when <strong>the</strong> minor premise is in fact<br />

necessary. 153<br />

If syllogistic premises are contingent in <strong>the</strong> compound sense, it does not follow<br />

that <strong>the</strong> consequent is contingent in <strong>the</strong> compound sense. Aristotelian uniform<br />

contingency syllogisms are valid for divided modals when <strong>the</strong> middle term is ampliated<br />

with respect to contingency. 154 Aristotelian first-figure mixed contingencyassertoric<br />

syllogisms are said to be valid for divided modals provided that <strong>the</strong><br />

contingency premise is not ampliated and <strong>the</strong> assertoric premise is assertoric simpliciter<br />

or ut nunc primo modo. 155 Because affirmative and negative contingency<br />

propositions with terms standing for actual things imply affirmative assertoric<br />

propositions and <strong>the</strong> contingent premises in mixed necessary and contingent syllogisms<br />

are <strong>of</strong> this type, <strong>the</strong> conclusions are assertoric. Aristotle seemingly denied<br />

this, but in fact he wanted to say that <strong>the</strong> assertoric conclusion was evident in<br />

negative moods and less apparent in affirmative moods. 156 The conclusions are<br />

to itself a natural contingency minor; op. cit. 27va-b. For Kilwardby’s discussion <strong>of</strong> contingency<br />

syllogisms, see also Thom 2007, ch. 6.<br />

152Campsall 11.58-9 (194); see also Lagerlund 2000, 74.<br />

15312.33-5 (205). Campsall states that mixed assertoric-necessity Baroco and mixed necessityassertoric<br />

Bocardo with necessary conclusions are syllogistically valid. When Aristotle did not<br />

accept <strong>the</strong>se, he did not mean that <strong>the</strong>y were not acceptable — it was only because <strong>the</strong> indirect<br />

pro<strong>of</strong> involved a possibility proper syllogism which was presented later in <strong>the</strong> Prior Analytics.<br />

The corresponding mixed necessity-assertoric Baroco and mixed assertoric-necessity Bocardo are<br />

valid consequences, but not syllogistic (14.16-19 (221-2)).<br />

15417.48-9, 17.70 (268-9, 274).<br />

15518.36-8 (283-4).<br />

15620.14-17 (304). Campsall does not deal with Aristotelian mixed contingency-necessity moods,<br />

apparently regarding <strong>the</strong>m immediately obvious when <strong>the</strong> contingency premises are not ampli-

Hooray! Your file is uploaded and ready to be published.

Saved successfully!

Ooh no, something went wrong!