22.06.2013 Views

Handbook of the History of Logic: - Fordham University Faculty

Handbook of the History of Logic: - Fordham University Faculty

Handbook of the History of Logic: - Fordham University Faculty

SHOW MORE
SHOW LESS

Create successful ePaper yourself

Turn your PDF publications into a flip-book with our unique Google optimized e-Paper software.

The Assimilation <strong>of</strong> Aristotelian and Arabic <strong>Logic</strong> up to <strong>the</strong> Later Thirteenth Century 327<br />

Given <strong>the</strong>se combinations <strong>the</strong>y present some general rules for <strong>the</strong> <strong>the</strong>ory. First <strong>of</strong><br />

all <strong>the</strong>re are five rules:<br />

1. There are no syllogisms from only particular, indefinite or singular premises.<br />

2. There are no syllogisms from only negative premises.<br />

3. If one <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> premises is particular <strong>the</strong>n a particular conclusion follows, but<br />

not its converse.<br />

4. If one <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> premises is negative <strong>the</strong>n a negative conclusion follows, and also<br />

its converse follows.<br />

5. The middle term must not be part <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> conclusion.<br />

The first figure has nine valid moods or forms <strong>of</strong> syllogisms. Four <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong>se have<br />

direct conclusions and five are indirect. In a direct conclusion <strong>the</strong> major extreme is<br />

predicated <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> minor extreme and in an indirect conclusion <strong>the</strong> converse holds.<br />

It became standard in <strong>the</strong> thirteenth century to treat <strong>the</strong> fourth figure introduced<br />

by Galen as an indirect form <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> first. The reason for this was to give a more<br />

faithful interpretation <strong>of</strong> Aristotle who does not mention <strong>the</strong> fourth figure.<br />

There are two rules that govern <strong>the</strong> first figure:<br />

6. If <strong>the</strong> minor premise is negative, <strong>the</strong>n no conclusion follows.<br />

7. If <strong>the</strong> major premise is particular, <strong>the</strong>n no conclusion follows.<br />

The four first syllogisms with direct conclusions are not given pro<strong>of</strong>s, since <strong>the</strong>y<br />

are perfect. Their validity is shown by reference to <strong>the</strong> dici de omni et nullo rules<br />

mentioned above. Dictum de omni governs <strong>the</strong> first mood (Barbara): 89<br />

I.<br />

Every B is A<br />

Every C is B<br />

Every C is A<br />

Dictum de nullo governs <strong>the</strong> second mood (Celarent):<br />

II.<br />

No B is A<br />

Every C is B<br />

No C is A<br />

The two o<strong>the</strong>r moods (Darii and Ferio) are reduced to <strong>the</strong>se two by <strong>the</strong> square <strong>of</strong><br />

opposition:<br />

89 For an explantion <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> names <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> valid syllogisms see below in this section.

Hooray! Your file is uploaded and ready to be published.

Saved successfully!

Ooh no, something went wrong!