22.06.2013 Views

Handbook of the History of Logic: - Fordham University Faculty

Handbook of the History of Logic: - Fordham University Faculty

Handbook of the History of Logic: - Fordham University Faculty

SHOW MORE
SHOW LESS

Create successful ePaper yourself

Turn your PDF publications into a flip-book with our unique Google optimized e-Paper software.

The Nominalist Semantics <strong>of</strong> Ockham and Buridan 399<br />

<strong>the</strong> time provided by <strong>the</strong> tense <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> verb and <strong>the</strong> context (<strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> utterance or,<br />

for example, <strong>the</strong> actual interpretation <strong>of</strong> a written predication). This last remark,<br />

however, introduces two o<strong>the</strong>r essential elements into <strong>the</strong> picture, namely, <strong>the</strong> verb<br />

needed for <strong>the</strong> predication, i.e., <strong>the</strong> copula, along with <strong>the</strong> time it co-signifies, and<br />

<strong>the</strong> supposition (reference) <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> subject.<br />

Supposition<br />

As we have seen, <strong>the</strong> via antiqua analysis <strong>of</strong> signification provides a number <strong>of</strong> different<br />

semantic values for any common term: <strong>the</strong>ir immediate significata (whe<strong>the</strong>r<br />

those should be identified as <strong>the</strong> formal concept, objective concept, or <strong>the</strong> common<br />

nature represented by <strong>the</strong>se concepts, or all <strong>the</strong>se in a sequence), <strong>the</strong>ir ultimate<br />

significata (<strong>the</strong> individualized natures, forms or “property instances” <strong>of</strong> individuals),<br />

and <strong>the</strong> merely indirectly signified individuals <strong>the</strong>mselves. Ordinarily, we use<br />

concrete common terms to talk about <strong>the</strong>se last-mentioned items. When we in fact<br />

use a term in a proposition to talk about <strong>the</strong>se, namely, about <strong>the</strong> individuals in<br />

which <strong>the</strong> ultimate significata <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> term are actual, <strong>the</strong>n <strong>the</strong> term is said to be in<br />

personal supposition, standing (or to use <strong>the</strong> common neologism, suppositing) for<br />

its personal supposita. When it stands for its (various) immediate significata (or<br />

even perhaps its ultimate significata or its significata in relation to its supposita,<br />

etc.), 20 <strong>the</strong>n it stands in simple supposition. And when it is used to stand for<br />

itself (or similar tokens <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> same type), <strong>the</strong>n it is said to be in material supposition.<br />

For example, ‘man’ in ‘Man is a species’ stands for <strong>the</strong> objective concept<br />

<strong>of</strong> humans, i.e., it has simple supposition, but in ‘A man is a rational animal’<br />

it has personal supposition, and in ‘Man is a noun in English’, it has material<br />

supposition.<br />

Attributing supposition, i.e., a context-dependent referring function to common<br />

terms stands in stark contrast with <strong>the</strong> Fregean conception, on <strong>the</strong> basis <strong>of</strong> which<br />

Peter Geach has repeatedly criticized <strong>the</strong> medieval idea <strong>of</strong> common personal supposition.<br />

21 However, one can clearly reconstruct this semantic function <strong>of</strong> common<br />

terms by using restricted variables, i.e., variables that are exactly like <strong>the</strong> variables<br />

<strong>of</strong> standard quantification <strong>the</strong>ory, except <strong>the</strong>y range not over <strong>the</strong> entire universe<br />

<strong>of</strong> discourse but only over <strong>the</strong> extension <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong>ir matrix. For instance, <strong>the</strong> sentence<br />

‘A man is a rational animal’ in this reconstruction would not have to be formalized<br />

by using an unrestricted variable bound by an existential quantifier, forcing us to<br />

introduce a conjunction to provide <strong>the</strong> correct truth conditions <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> original. In-<br />

20 Walter Burley, for example, presents an elaborate system <strong>of</strong> distinctions for various sorts <strong>of</strong><br />

simple supposition in his Tractatus de suppositionibus, in S.F. Brown, “Walter Burleigh’s Treatise<br />

De suppositionibus and its Influence on William <strong>of</strong> Ockham”, Franciscan Studies, 32 (1972), pp.<br />

15-64. he also changed his mind about parts <strong>of</strong> his doctrine in his On <strong>the</strong> Purity <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> Art<br />

<strong>of</strong> <strong>Logic</strong>. For details, see Spade, P.V., “Walter Burley on <strong>the</strong> Kinds <strong>of</strong> Simple Supposition”,<br />

Vivarium, 37(1999), pp. 41-59. But we find similar distinctions in o<strong>the</strong>r “older” authors as well.<br />

21 See Geach, P. T., Reference and Generality, Cornell <strong>University</strong> Press: Ithaca, NY, 1962, c.<br />

2, sect. 28, pp, 34-36; Peter Geach, “Nominalism,” Sophia 3(1964), pp. 3-14, reprinted in his<br />

<strong>Logic</strong> Matters, Berkeley and Los Angeles: <strong>University</strong> <strong>of</strong> California Press, 1980, pp. 298-301.

Hooray! Your file is uploaded and ready to be published.

Saved successfully!

Ooh no, something went wrong!