22.06.2013 Views

Handbook of the History of Logic: - Fordham University Faculty

Handbook of the History of Logic: - Fordham University Faculty

Handbook of the History of Logic: - Fordham University Faculty

SHOW MORE
SHOW LESS

Create successful ePaper yourself

Turn your PDF publications into a flip-book with our unique Google optimized e-Paper software.

Port Royal: The Stirrings <strong>of</strong> Modernity 677<br />

to do this, since <strong>the</strong>y seem to recognize some unity in complex ideas and this unity<br />

would serve well as what Russell later called propositional concepts or “unasserted<br />

propositions”. 16 By <strong>the</strong>ir own criteria, <strong>the</strong>re is no assertion when I say simply “<strong>the</strong><br />

visible world,” since <strong>the</strong>re is no act <strong>of</strong> affirming or denying anything. I could, for<br />

example, be contemplating denying its existence. They could <strong>the</strong>n have said that<br />

<strong>the</strong> act <strong>of</strong> asserting was <strong>the</strong> act <strong>of</strong> judging that <strong>the</strong> parts <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> complex idea go<br />

toge<strong>the</strong>r, and <strong>the</strong> act <strong>of</strong> negating involved judging <strong>the</strong>y did not. The propositional<br />

concepts would <strong>the</strong>n have a unity, i.e. <strong>the</strong> unity <strong>of</strong> a complex term, though not one<br />

created by <strong>the</strong> asserting will. Unfortunately, <strong>the</strong>y did not address this difficulty<br />

in this manner.<br />

The Port-Royalists were taken by <strong>the</strong> fact that <strong>the</strong> sentence,<br />

Invisible God created <strong>the</strong> visible world<br />

was equivalent to <strong>the</strong> sentence,<br />

God, who is invisible, created <strong>the</strong> world, which is visible.<br />

This last sentence contains verbs occurring as verbs and it seems that someone<br />

who states this is committed to <strong>the</strong> truth <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> claims “God is invisible” and “<strong>the</strong><br />

world is visible”. With respect to <strong>the</strong> proposition “Invisible God created <strong>the</strong> visible<br />

world,” <strong>the</strong>se o<strong>the</strong>r propositions are probably better understood as presupposed<br />

ra<strong>the</strong>r than asserted. There is a place in <strong>the</strong> <strong>Logic</strong> where Arnauld and Nicole<br />

allow that a proposition can still be true even though <strong>the</strong> incidental propositions<br />

are false:<br />

...<strong>the</strong>falsity<strong>of</strong><strong>the</strong>incidentalproposition does not ordinarily preclude<br />

<strong>the</strong> truth <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> main proposition. For example, “Alexander who was<br />

<strong>the</strong> son <strong>of</strong> Philip defeated <strong>the</strong> Persian.” This proposition should be<br />

considered true even if Alexander was not <strong>the</strong> son <strong>of</strong> Philip, because<br />

<strong>the</strong> affirmation <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> principal proposition affects only Alexander, and<br />

what is joined to it incidentally, although false, does not prevent it from<br />

being true that Alexander defeated <strong>the</strong> Persians. (125)<br />

However, <strong>the</strong>y hold that when <strong>the</strong> incidental proposition is related as in “Alexander<br />

<strong>the</strong> son <strong>of</strong> Philip was <strong>the</strong> grandson <strong>of</strong> Amintas” <strong>the</strong> falsity <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> incidental<br />

proposition would make <strong>the</strong> principal proposition false. Unfortunately, <strong>the</strong>y did<br />

not elaborate this example, for it is not clear why, for example, if Amintas had<br />

had two sons, Philip and Hector, and unbeknown to everyone Alexander was <strong>the</strong><br />

son <strong>of</strong> Hector, we would not gloss <strong>the</strong> example <strong>the</strong> same as <strong>the</strong> one above. In <strong>the</strong><br />

first section, Arnauld and Nicole point out what <strong>the</strong>y call <strong>the</strong> ambiguity <strong>of</strong> such<br />

expressions as “<strong>the</strong> true religion”. They say,<br />

16 The example Russell uses is “The death <strong>of</strong> Caesar” as opposed to “Caesar died”. It is clear<br />

from <strong>the</strong> Port-Royal discussion in Part II Chapter 2 that <strong>the</strong> first <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong>se would simply be a<br />

complex idea and not a proposition. See especially p.111.

Hooray! Your file is uploaded and ready to be published.

Saved successfully!

Ooh no, something went wrong!