22.06.2013 Views

Handbook of the History of Logic: - Fordham University Faculty

Handbook of the History of Logic: - Fordham University Faculty

Handbook of the History of Logic: - Fordham University Faculty

SHOW MORE
SHOW LESS

Create successful ePaper yourself

Turn your PDF publications into a flip-book with our unique Google optimized e-Paper software.

<strong>Logic</strong> in <strong>the</strong> 14 th Century after Ockham 447<br />

insolubles, and consequences. Unfortunately, so far only his treatises on <strong>the</strong> properties<br />

<strong>of</strong> terms have received a modern edition [Bos, 1983]. Marsilius will be a<br />

central figure in our discussion on supposition below.<br />

John <strong>of</strong> Holland is ano<strong>the</strong>r interesting case <strong>of</strong> an author somehow belonging<br />

to both <strong>the</strong> Continental and <strong>the</strong> British traditions. While <strong>the</strong>re is no conclusive<br />

evidence to <strong>the</strong> effect that he did study at Oxford, his familiarity with <strong>the</strong> works <strong>of</strong><br />

some Oxford logicians such as Heytesbury and Bradwardine is an indication that<br />

this might have been <strong>the</strong> case (cf. [Bos, 1985, *14*]). In fact, little is known about<br />

him, but we do know that he studied in Prague 15 , and was later to become Dean<br />

<strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> faculty <strong>of</strong> arts in Prague in 1369. His treatises on supposition, fallacies,<br />

obligation and insolubilia have received modern editions [John <strong>of</strong> Holland, 1985].<br />

Peter <strong>of</strong> Ailly was a Parisian master who wrote his best known work in 1372,<br />

his Concepts and Insolubles [Ailly, 1980]. This work deals with mental language<br />

and in particular <strong>the</strong> signification <strong>of</strong> mental and spoken terms, and, as <strong>the</strong> title<br />

says, with insolubles. His definition <strong>of</strong> signification was to be very influential in<br />

<strong>the</strong> 15 th century. Although influential for subsequent developments, Ailly will not<br />

be treated in any <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> analyses to follow, since his main contribution to logic<br />

concerns insolubilia and semantic notions such as that <strong>of</strong> signification, which for<br />

reasons <strong>of</strong> space will not be dealt with here.<br />

Besides France, Britain, Central Europe and Italy, <strong>the</strong>re was also vivid intellectual<br />

activity in Spain; indeed, a handful <strong>of</strong> universities were founded in Spain in<br />

<strong>the</strong> 14 th century. But contrasting with <strong>the</strong> 15 th and 16 th centuries, when Spain<br />

was to become one <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> main centers for original work within <strong>the</strong> Scholastic<br />

tradition, we know <strong>of</strong> no Spanish logicians in <strong>the</strong> 14 th century having had <strong>the</strong><br />

same influence and importance as later authors such as Domingo de Soto. Worth<br />

noticing, however, is that <strong>the</strong> (o<strong>the</strong>rwise) famous St. Vincent Ferrer composed<br />

an interesting treatise on supposition around 1372 (edited in [Trentman, 1977]).<br />

Particularly significant is <strong>the</strong> fact that St. Vincent Ferrer went through his whole<br />

student career in his native Spain; so while he seemed to be acquainted with most<br />

<strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> important logical texts <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> 14 th century, he was in practice outside <strong>the</strong><br />

circle <strong>of</strong> influence <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> main centers, and claimed that his main source <strong>of</strong> inspiration<br />

was St. Thomas Aquinas. St. Vincent will be briefly mentioned in <strong>the</strong><br />

section on supposition below.<br />

By contrast, an author such as Blaise <strong>of</strong> Parme indicates that, in Italy, <strong>the</strong><br />

‘usual’ 14 th century authors were indeed very influential, such as Ockham and<br />

Buridan. The logic taught at Italian universities <strong>the</strong>n was referred to (and dismissed)<br />

by humanists such as Petrarca as ‘Ockhamist logic’, and Blaise is perhaps<br />

<strong>the</strong> most prominent example <strong>the</strong>re<strong>of</strong>. His only surviving logical text is a set <strong>of</strong><br />

questions on Peter <strong>of</strong> Spain’s Tractatus (edited recently by J. Biard and G. Federici<br />

Vescovini — [Blaise <strong>of</strong> Parme, 2001]), which is in many ways idiosyncratic<br />

for a 14 th century logical work in that it does not treat <strong>of</strong> supposition and o<strong>the</strong>r<br />

typical 14 th century topics. It does have a section on consequence, but it does not<br />

15 But remember that, unlike o<strong>the</strong>r Eastern European universities, Oxford logic was quite<br />

influential in Prague, so John’s knowledge <strong>of</strong> British logic may have been acquired in Prague.

Hooray! Your file is uploaded and ready to be published.

Saved successfully!

Ooh no, something went wrong!