22.06.2013 Views

Handbook of the History of Logic: - Fordham University Faculty

Handbook of the History of Logic: - Fordham University Faculty

Handbook of the History of Logic: - Fordham University Faculty

SHOW MORE
SHOW LESS

Create successful ePaper yourself

Turn your PDF publications into a flip-book with our unique Google optimized e-Paper software.

Peter Abelard and His Contemporaries 91<br />

former. Clearly, on Abelard’s account, traditional intuitions about <strong>the</strong> inherent<br />

prestige <strong>of</strong> generality are challenged. Instead <strong>of</strong> generality’s being characteristic<br />

<strong>of</strong> a higher order <strong>of</strong> being (<strong>the</strong> shared form), it is characteristic <strong>of</strong> a less complete<br />

kind <strong>of</strong> representation.<br />

Universal names, he says, “signify diverse things by nomination not by constituting<br />

an understanding that arises (surgentem) fromthose but by<br />

pertains (pertinentem) to those single things” [Abelard,<br />

1919, p. 19 (7–9)]. A general understanding is not read <strong>of</strong>f <strong>of</strong> things directly, but<br />

is partially <strong>the</strong> product <strong>of</strong> human cognitive processing. Its ability to be useful lies<br />

in its ability to pertain to things even while failing to be a copy <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong>m point<br />

for point. This ability to pertain in spite <strong>of</strong> that failing stems from <strong>the</strong> fact that<br />

<strong>the</strong>re is something about <strong>the</strong> things <strong>the</strong>mselves that allows <strong>the</strong>m to be partially<br />

represented in <strong>the</strong> same way. There is, for example, something about Socrates and<br />

Plato which allows <strong>the</strong>m both to be represented by an image or figure or form <strong>of</strong><br />

humanity. What that is, <strong>of</strong> course, is <strong>the</strong>ir being in <strong>the</strong> same status. Obviously,<br />

an account <strong>of</strong> abstraction like Abelard’s could easily evolve into a view about<br />

<strong>the</strong> non-objectivity <strong>of</strong> general names, but he will have none <strong>of</strong> that. The status<br />

is what makes objectivity possible. That is why, when Abelard asks whe<strong>the</strong>r a<br />

word is called common “according to <strong>the</strong> common cause in which things agree<br />

or according to <strong>the</strong> common understanding” [Abelard, 1919, p. 19 (17–20)], he<br />

gives <strong>the</strong> nod to <strong>the</strong> former [Abelard, 1919, p. 24 (35–37)]. The common cause<br />

in which things agree is <strong>the</strong> status. This common cause is <strong>the</strong> prior, factual basis<br />

for applicability <strong>of</strong> general terms; <strong>the</strong> common understanding — <strong>the</strong> intellectus<br />

— is <strong>the</strong> subsequent cognitive response to that fact which actually triggers <strong>the</strong><br />

production <strong>of</strong> that term. The intellectus explains how general terms are formed,<br />

but <strong>the</strong> status explains how <strong>the</strong>y are possible in <strong>the</strong> first place.<br />

With this semantic account <strong>of</strong> general terms, a doctrine <strong>of</strong> shared forms no<br />

longer belongs to <strong>the</strong> subject matter <strong>of</strong> logic. The true subject matter emerges:<br />

logic is concerned not with relations <strong>of</strong> shared forms (man, animal) but with relations<br />

between linguistic items (“man,” “animal”). But this conclusion must itself<br />

be refined to avoid trivializing <strong>the</strong> discipline. It becomes important to understand<br />

what exactly a word is. If a word is taken just as spoken, and as nothing but an<br />

evanescent sound pattern, <strong>the</strong>n this focus on words means that instead <strong>of</strong> being<br />

about <strong>the</strong> perduring realities <strong>of</strong> shared forms, logic deals only with <strong>the</strong>se transitory<br />

and vanishing sounds. In <strong>the</strong> derisive phrasing <strong>of</strong> Anselm [Anselm, 1946, p. 9],<br />

logic devolves into <strong>the</strong> study <strong>of</strong> mere flatus vocis, that is, into <strong>the</strong> study <strong>of</strong> what<br />

is merely <strong>the</strong> breath <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> word, its physical properties. The need to avoid this<br />

result leads Abelard into one <strong>of</strong> his subtlest innovations: his distinction between<br />

sermo and vox. Both can be translated as “word,” but <strong>the</strong> former encourages a<br />

conception <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> word as sound invested with meaning, while <strong>the</strong> latter does not.<br />

The sermo compares to <strong>the</strong> vox, Abelard argues, as <strong>the</strong> finished statue compares<br />

to <strong>the</strong> stone from which it is carved [Abelard, 1933, p. 522 (22–27)]. The two<br />

are in one sense <strong>the</strong> same thing, because <strong>the</strong> statue is materially indistinguishable<br />

from its stone. But in ano<strong>the</strong>r sense <strong>the</strong> two are different because <strong>the</strong>re is at least

Hooray! Your file is uploaded and ready to be published.

Saved successfully!

Ooh no, something went wrong!