22.06.2013 Views

Handbook of the History of Logic: - Fordham University Faculty

Handbook of the History of Logic: - Fordham University Faculty

Handbook of the History of Logic: - Fordham University Faculty

SHOW MORE
SHOW LESS

You also want an ePaper? Increase the reach of your titles

YUMPU automatically turns print PDFs into web optimized ePapers that Google loves.

618 E. Jennifer Ashworth<br />

rejected and <strong>the</strong> fourth figure accepted. 47<br />

2 THE FATE OF THE MEDIEVAL CONTRIBUTIONS TO LOGIC<br />

So far I have considered only Aristotle and commentaries on Aristotle. However,<br />

this is somewhat misleading so far as university instruction is concerned, since <strong>the</strong><br />

material in question was aimed at more senior students, including those studying<br />

for <strong>the</strong> M.A. degree. Medieval universities exposed first-year arts students to<br />

a wide range <strong>of</strong> logical writings, mostly contemporary; and during <strong>the</strong> sixteenth<br />

century, although Italian universities continued a tradition <strong>of</strong> reading Aristotle and<br />

his commentators directly, 48 o<strong>the</strong>r universities turned more and more to textbooks<br />

<strong>of</strong> one kind and ano<strong>the</strong>r. What I have considered so far is misleading for ano<strong>the</strong>r<br />

reason as well, since I have totally ignored <strong>the</strong> development <strong>of</strong> areas <strong>of</strong> logic not<br />

discussed by Aristotle. It is now time to remedy <strong>the</strong>se defects, and I shall begin by<br />

outlining <strong>the</strong> specifically medieval contributions to logic which have been discussed<br />

in previous chapters.<br />

One <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> features <strong>of</strong> medieval logic was <strong>the</strong> production <strong>of</strong> independent texts,<br />

each focussing on a particular topic. These texts were regarded as complete in<br />

<strong>the</strong>mselves, and as not needing any justification in terms <strong>of</strong> Aristotelian logic.<br />

They can be organized into three groups. The core <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> first group is formed<br />

by <strong>the</strong> so-called parva logicalia, or treatises dealing with <strong>the</strong> properties <strong>of</strong> terms,<br />

including <strong>the</strong>ir reference in various contexts. Here we find tracts on supposition,<br />

on relative terms, on ampliation, appellation, restriction and distribution. These<br />

core treatises were supplemented in three ways. <strong>Logic</strong>ians wrote about syncategorematic<br />

terms, that is, <strong>the</strong> logical particles such as ‘all’, ‘some’, and ‘not’, which<br />

determine <strong>the</strong> logical structure <strong>of</strong> a proposition. They wrote about exponible<br />

terms, that is, those logical particles such as ‘except’ and ‘only’ whose presence<br />

requires <strong>the</strong> analysis <strong>of</strong> an apparently simple categorical proposition into several<br />

conjoined propositions. Finally, <strong>the</strong>y wrote about <strong>the</strong> pro<strong>of</strong> <strong>of</strong> terms, or <strong>the</strong> ways<br />

in which <strong>the</strong> truth-conditions <strong>of</strong> propositions are affected by <strong>the</strong> presence <strong>of</strong> exponible<br />

terms, <strong>of</strong> modal terms such as ‘necessary’ and ‘possible’, or <strong>of</strong> epistemic<br />

terms such as ‘knows’ and ‘believes’. Obviously <strong>the</strong>re is a good deal <strong>of</strong> overlap<br />

between writings on syncategorematic terms, on exponibles, and on <strong>the</strong> pro<strong>of</strong> <strong>of</strong><br />

terms, since one and <strong>the</strong> same particle could be discussed in all three types <strong>of</strong><br />

treatise. The second group contains <strong>the</strong> ‘three tracts <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> moderns’, that is, <strong>the</strong><br />

treatises on consequences, obligations and insolubles. 49 The third group is formed<br />

by <strong>the</strong> treatises on sophismata in which problematic or puzzling statements were<br />

47For details, see E. J. Ashworth, “Some Notes on Syllogistic in <strong>the</strong> Sixteenth and Seventeenth<br />

Centuries”, Notre Dame Journal <strong>of</strong> Formal <strong>Logic</strong> 11 (1970), 17–33.<br />

48Schmitt, “Philosophy and Science in Sixteenth-Century Universities: Some Preliminary Comments,”<br />

p. 508.<br />

49For an interesting discussion <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> way in which <strong>the</strong> phrase ‘<strong>Logic</strong>a modernorum’ has been<br />

extended in recent times to refer to all <strong>the</strong> new developments <strong>of</strong> medieval logic, see N. W. Gilbert,<br />

“Ockham, Wyclif and <strong>the</strong> ‘via moderna’,” Miscellanea Mediaevalia 9 (1974), pp. 111–115.

Hooray! Your file is uploaded and ready to be published.

Saved successfully!

Ooh no, something went wrong!