22.06.2013 Views

Handbook of the History of Logic: - Fordham University Faculty

Handbook of the History of Logic: - Fordham University Faculty

Handbook of the History of Logic: - Fordham University Faculty

SHOW MORE
SHOW LESS

You also want an ePaper? Increase the reach of your titles

YUMPU automatically turns print PDFs into web optimized ePapers that Google loves.

352 Ria van der Lecq<br />

<strong>the</strong> mind, extra-mental objects. In fact, he held this position all his life. But before<br />

<strong>the</strong> 1260s he seems to identify concept and intelligible species (mental image).<br />

In his commentary on <strong>the</strong> Sentences Aquinas distinguishes between three kinds<br />

<strong>of</strong> names. First, <strong>the</strong>re are names for extra-mental things. When <strong>the</strong> intellect<br />

conceives a likeness <strong>of</strong> an extra-mental thing, for example a stone, <strong>the</strong> word ‘stone’<br />

signifies that mental image, which is elsewhere called ‘intelligible species’. This<br />

image is not simply a picture <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> extra-mental object, but an abstraction: it does<br />

not contain individual features. Second, <strong>the</strong>re are names that signify intentions<br />

like ‘genus’ or ‘species’, with only a remote foundation in reality. Finally, <strong>the</strong>re<br />

are names that signify concepts without foundation in reality, like <strong>the</strong> concept <strong>of</strong><br />

‘chimera’. In <strong>the</strong> first and <strong>the</strong> third case names signify concepts in <strong>the</strong>ir function <strong>of</strong><br />

images <strong>of</strong> existing or non-existing things; in <strong>the</strong> second case <strong>the</strong>y signify concepts<br />

<strong>of</strong> concepts. 19<br />

The older Thomas Aquinas: Primary signification <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> concept<br />

In his more mature writings 20 Aquinas does not identify intelligible species and<br />

concept any more. 21 The concept — or ‘<strong>the</strong> thing conceived’, also called intentio<br />

intellecta 22 — is <strong>the</strong> essence <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> extra-mental object as it is abstracted by our<br />

intellect from <strong>the</strong> object’s being. For example, <strong>the</strong> concept ‘man’ is <strong>the</strong> result<br />

<strong>of</strong> an abstraction <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> essence <strong>of</strong> a man, leaving his particular existence out<br />

<strong>of</strong> consideration. 23 This concept is signified by <strong>the</strong> spoken word ‘man’. It is<br />

also that which is understood. Individuals cannot be primarily signified, because<br />

<strong>the</strong>y cannot be primarily understood. Unlike <strong>the</strong> sensitive faculty <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> soul, <strong>the</strong><br />

intellective faculty does not have a direct cognition <strong>of</strong> extra-mental objects: it<br />

understands by virtue <strong>of</strong> an intelligible species and its object is <strong>the</strong> concept or<br />

mental word (verbum mentis).<br />

In <strong>the</strong> scholarly literature <strong>the</strong>re is a discussion about <strong>the</strong> interpretation <strong>of</strong><br />

Aquinas’s mature <strong>the</strong>ory. Some authors state that <strong>the</strong> mental word (also called<br />

‘intention’) should be identified with <strong>the</strong> extra-mental thing ins<strong>of</strong>ar as it is understood;<br />

o<strong>the</strong>rs say that it is a product <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> intellect completely distinct from<br />

<strong>the</strong> extra-mental thing. 24 As we shall see below, Duns Scotus seems to refer to<br />

<strong>the</strong> first interpretation: words signify things ins<strong>of</strong>ar as <strong>the</strong>y are understood, but<br />

both interpretations have <strong>the</strong>ir advocates. 25 It should be noted, however, that in<br />

medieval philosophical writings <strong>the</strong> terms ‘concept’ and ‘intention’ are semantically<br />

ambivalent in <strong>the</strong> sense that a concept always includes what it intends to<br />

signify. 26 Concepts always have a foundation in reality, directly or indirectly. The<br />

19See <strong>the</strong> paragraph on second intentions in this chapter.<br />

20Especially his commentary on Peri hermeneias, <strong>the</strong>Summa <strong>the</strong>ologiae and De potentia<br />

21E.g. Thomas Aquinas, Summa <strong>the</strong>ologiae I.82.2.<br />

22See below, p. 372.<br />

23This is <strong>the</strong> so-called ‘non-precisive abstraction’. Precisive abstraction is <strong>the</strong> abstraction <strong>of</strong><br />

<strong>the</strong> form; <strong>the</strong> result would be <strong>the</strong> concept ‘humanity’.<br />

24Cf. Pini [1999, p. 49], who speaks <strong>of</strong> a ‘realistic’ vs. a ‘mentalistic’ interpretation.<br />

25See Pini [1999, pp.49–50] for examples.<br />

26De Rijk [2005, pp. 24-5] and passim.

Hooray! Your file is uploaded and ready to be published.

Saved successfully!

Ooh no, something went wrong!