22.06.2013 Views

Handbook of the History of Logic: - Fordham University Faculty

Handbook of the History of Logic: - Fordham University Faculty

Handbook of the History of Logic: - Fordham University Faculty

SHOW MORE
SHOW LESS

You also want an ePaper? Increase the reach of your titles

YUMPU automatically turns print PDFs into web optimized ePapers that Google loves.

Medieval Modal Theories and Modal <strong>Logic</strong> 569<br />

ing impossible follows, but he had in mind actualization in <strong>the</strong> history <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong><br />

actual world. The denial <strong>of</strong> an omnitemporally actual state <strong>of</strong> affairs is said to<br />

be impossible. In <strong>the</strong> thirteenth century, some thinkers qualified Aristotle’s characterization<br />

<strong>of</strong> possibility as something which can be assumed as actual without<br />

contradiction by explaining that possibilities referring to <strong>the</strong> same moment <strong>of</strong> time<br />

are not necessarily compossible in <strong>the</strong> sense that <strong>the</strong>y could be actual at <strong>the</strong> same<br />

time. In Scotus’s <strong>the</strong>ory, actualizability as a criterion <strong>of</strong> possibility does not refer<br />

to <strong>the</strong> already existing actual world, nor is it explained by referring to prospective<br />

options <strong>of</strong> which <strong>the</strong> unrealized will disappear, as in <strong>the</strong> <strong>the</strong>ories <strong>of</strong> diachronic<br />

modalities. Temporally definite possibilities are primarily treated as referring to<br />

alternatives, as is shown by <strong>the</strong> definition <strong>of</strong> a contingent state <strong>of</strong> affairs: ‘I do<br />

not call something contingent because it is not always or necessarily <strong>the</strong> case, but<br />

because its opposite could be actual at <strong>the</strong> very moment when it occurs’.<br />

In <strong>the</strong> fourteenth century, many authors followed Scotus in explicating <strong>the</strong><br />

meaning <strong>of</strong> modal terms by referring to simultaneous alternatives as <strong>the</strong> basic<br />

model. This is also reflected in <strong>the</strong> reformulation <strong>of</strong> modal logic with <strong>the</strong> systematic<br />

distinction between modalities de dicto and de re and <strong>the</strong> division <strong>of</strong><br />

de re modalities into those with actual subject terms and those with non-actual<br />

subject terms. The basic notion was that <strong>of</strong> logical possibility which was distinguished<br />

from <strong>the</strong> more restricted notion <strong>of</strong> natural possibility. John Buridan’s<br />

<strong>the</strong>ory <strong>of</strong> modal consequences is considered as one <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> greatest achievements<br />

<strong>of</strong> medieval logic. Aristotle’s modal syllogistics was regarded as a fragmentary<br />

<strong>the</strong>ory in which <strong>the</strong> different types <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> fine structure <strong>of</strong> modal statements were<br />

not distinguished. Contrary to thirteenth-century approaches, Ockham, Buridan<br />

and <strong>the</strong>ir followers did not try to reconstruct Aristotle’s <strong>the</strong>ory as such into a<br />

uniform system. The new modal paradigms which show some similarities to <strong>the</strong><br />

background ideas <strong>of</strong> possible worlds semantics also influenced fourteenth century<br />

logic <strong>of</strong> discourse (obligations logic) and <strong>the</strong> treatments <strong>of</strong> applied modal logic,<br />

<strong>the</strong> logic <strong>of</strong> knowledge and belief and <strong>the</strong> logic <strong>of</strong> norms.<br />

Primary Literature<br />

BIBLIOGRAPHY<br />

[Alan <strong>of</strong> Lille, 1981] Alan <strong>of</strong> Lille. Regulae caelestis iuris, ed. N.M. Häring, Archives d’histoire<br />

doctrinale et littéraire du moyen âge 78 (1981), 97-226.<br />

[Albert <strong>of</strong> Saxony, 1502] Albert <strong>of</strong> Saxony. Sophismata (Paris, 1502).<br />

[Albert <strong>the</strong> Great, 1890a] Albert <strong>the</strong> Great. Commentarius in Perihermenias, inOpera omnia,<br />

ed. A. Borgnet, vol. I (Paris: Vivès, 1890).<br />

[Albert <strong>the</strong> Great, 1890b] Albert <strong>the</strong> Great. Commentarius in Librum I Priorum Analyticorum,<br />

in Opera omnia, ed. A. Borgnet, vol. I (Paris: Vivès, 1890).<br />

[Alexander <strong>of</strong> Aphrodisias, 1883] Alexander <strong>of</strong> Aphrodisias. In Aristotelis Analyticorum priorum<br />

librum I commentarium, ed. M. Wallies, Commentaria in Aristotelem Graeca 2.1 (Berlin:<br />

Reimer, 1883).<br />

[Ammonius, 1961] Ammonius. Commentaire sur le Peri hermeneias d’Aristote. Traduction de<br />

Guillaume de Moerbeke, ed. G. Verbeke, Corpus Latinum Commentariorum in Aristotelem<br />

Graecorum (Louvain: Publications Universitaires, Paris: Béatrice-Nauwelaerts, 1961); <strong>the</strong><br />

Greek text is edited by A. Busse in Commentaria in Aristotelem Graeca 4.5 (Berlin, 1897).

Hooray! Your file is uploaded and ready to be published.

Saved successfully!

Ooh no, something went wrong!