22.06.2013 Views

Handbook of the History of Logic: - Fordham University Faculty

Handbook of the History of Logic: - Fordham University Faculty

Handbook of the History of Logic: - Fordham University Faculty

SHOW MORE
SHOW LESS

You also want an ePaper? Increase the reach of your titles

YUMPU automatically turns print PDFs into web optimized ePapers that Google loves.

Developments in <strong>the</strong> Fifteenth and Sixteenth Centuries 639<br />

semantic link between particular non-logical terms. I dub <strong>the</strong>se ‘non-formal’. Such<br />

arguments were discussed under <strong>the</strong> heading <strong>of</strong> ‘materially valid consequences’, by<br />

those logicians who continued to include sections on consequences in <strong>the</strong>ir texts,<br />

and who used <strong>the</strong> substitution criterion <strong>of</strong> formality. 144 In <strong>the</strong> case <strong>of</strong> arguments<br />

that are not deductively valid but are none<strong>the</strong>less acceptable, we might be talking<br />

about incomplete arguments, notably enthymemes, that need to be re-expressed as<br />

formal deductive arguments, or we might be talking about those arguments whose<br />

premisses merely support <strong>the</strong> conclusion, or in some way make it reasonable to<br />

accept <strong>the</strong> conclusion. Only <strong>the</strong> latter are properly dubbed ‘informal’.<br />

At this point, we face ano<strong>the</strong>r problem. As discussed in Part One, Agricola<br />

and Ramus had excluded maxims and rules from <strong>the</strong> parts <strong>of</strong> dialectic devoted to<br />

invention. This reduced or even eliminated <strong>the</strong> room for informal argumentation<br />

connected with <strong>the</strong> Topics. Moreover, Agricola had accepted <strong>the</strong> four standard<br />

types <strong>of</strong> argumentation as <strong>the</strong> subject <strong>of</strong> dialectical judgement, while Ramus insisted<br />

that <strong>the</strong> syllogism, whe<strong>the</strong>r Aristotelian as in <strong>the</strong> Scholae, or reformed, as<br />

in his Dialectica, was <strong>the</strong> general object <strong>of</strong> discussion under judgement. We also<br />

have to take into account <strong>the</strong> rejection <strong>of</strong> specifically medieval material by many<br />

sixteenth-century logicians. This meant that in a simplified logic manual <strong>the</strong>re<br />

was no discussion <strong>of</strong> types <strong>of</strong> conditional statement or <strong>of</strong> types <strong>of</strong> consequence,<br />

any more than <strong>the</strong>re was serious discussion <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> standard types <strong>of</strong> argumentation.<br />

Accordingly, it is only in those texts that are more heavily scholastic and<br />

Aristotelian in <strong>the</strong>ir approach that we find anything more than a hand-waving hint<br />

that <strong>the</strong>re are indeed informal argumentative devices. I will consider just a few<br />

examples.<br />

I will start with conditionals and consequences. In his commentary on Peter<br />

<strong>of</strong> Spain, Eck divides consequences into those that are merely inferential (illativa<br />

tantum), those that are both inferential and convincing (illativa et probativa),<br />

and those that are merely convincing (probativa tantum). Merely convincing consequences<br />

are those in which <strong>the</strong> antecedent does not entail <strong>the</strong> conclusion, but<br />

support it with reference to <strong>the</strong> Topics. They are persuasive, and are used in ethics<br />

and rhetoric. 145 That is, <strong>the</strong>y do not really belong to logic.<br />

Petrus Fonseca is less dismissive. Contrary to <strong>the</strong> view held by Peter <strong>of</strong> Spain<br />

that all conditionals are ei<strong>the</strong>r necessary or impossible, Fonseca, like Nifo before<br />

him, 146 allows for conditional statements that are contingent; 147 and he also argues<br />

that that while all formal consequences are necessary, material consequences can<br />

144 For <strong>the</strong> issues here, see <strong>the</strong> previous chapter on medieval <strong>the</strong>ories <strong>of</strong> consequence. For those<br />

who used <strong>the</strong> containment criterion <strong>of</strong> formality, <strong>the</strong> labels attached to what I call non-formal<br />

consequences will differ.<br />

145 Johannes Eckius, In summulas Petri Hispani (Augsburg, 1516), f. c vb. “Probativa tantum<br />

est in qua antecedens non de necessitate infert consequens, tamen probat probabiliter et topice.”<br />

He subsequently adds “consequentiam probativam non esse simpliciter bonam consequentiam<br />

sed esse persuasivam, et in moralibus ac rhetoricis multum frequentatam, ut Hupertus fuit solus<br />

cum Ca<strong>the</strong>rina in loco suspecto, ergo stupravit eam”.<br />

146 Niphus, Dialectica ludicra, f.78vb,f.79rb.<br />

147 Fonseca, Instituições Dialécticas, p. 198.

Hooray! Your file is uploaded and ready to be published.

Saved successfully!

Ooh no, something went wrong!