22.06.2013 Views

Handbook of the History of Logic: - Fordham University Faculty

Handbook of the History of Logic: - Fordham University Faculty

Handbook of the History of Logic: - Fordham University Faculty

SHOW MORE
SHOW LESS

You also want an ePaper? Increase the reach of your titles

YUMPU automatically turns print PDFs into web optimized ePapers that Google loves.

The Assimilation <strong>of</strong> Aristotelian and Arabic <strong>Logic</strong> up to <strong>the</strong> Later Thirteenth Century 341<br />

predicate to ei<strong>the</strong>r (i) at least one thing <strong>of</strong> each kind under <strong>the</strong> subject, or (ii)<br />

to each individual thing belonging to <strong>the</strong> subject. William is not explicit as to<br />

which <strong>of</strong> (i) and (ii) he prefers. The example ‘Every dog is an animal’ is analyzed<br />

in (i) into a conjunction <strong>of</strong> ‘A collie is an animal’, and ‘A puddle is an animal’,<br />

etc. In (ii), it is analyzed into ‘Fido is an animal’, and ‘Spot is an animal’, etc.<br />

William’s discussion <strong>of</strong> ‘Every’ or ‘All’ is very detailed and goes through all cases<br />

and examples in which this term functions as a syncategorematic term.<br />

William seems to be one <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> first logicians to treat ‘is’ as a syncategorematic<br />

term. The first question he addresses is whe<strong>the</strong>r ‘is’ pertains to <strong>the</strong> composition <strong>of</strong><br />

<strong>the</strong> subject and <strong>the</strong> predicate or if it pertains to <strong>the</strong> predicate. To explain this he<br />

recalls <strong>the</strong> distinction between ‘signification’ and ‘consignification’, and explains<br />

that ‘is’ is not really a third part <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> proposition, that is, a composition, since it<br />

signifies that which is said <strong>of</strong> something o<strong>the</strong>r than itself and this is <strong>the</strong> predicate,<br />

but it does consignify <strong>the</strong> composition, which is <strong>the</strong> function <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> copula.<br />

‘Is’ is also equivocal for sometimes it indicates actual being (esse actuale) and<br />

at o<strong>the</strong>r times conditional being (esse habituale), which is something with some<br />

nature, but which does not actually exist although it could. If in ‘Every human<br />

being is an animal’ ‘is’ is taken in <strong>the</strong> first way, <strong>the</strong>n it is false when no humans<br />

exist. If it is taken in <strong>the</strong> second way, <strong>the</strong>n it is true no matter whe<strong>the</strong>r <strong>the</strong>re<br />

are any human or not. In this way, William commits himself to possibilia or to<br />

things that could exist but does not. He notes himself that this amounts to saying<br />

that things that do not exist but could have a diminished kind <strong>of</strong> being (esse<br />

diminutum).<br />

I will end by noting some interesting things said by William about modal terms<br />

like ‘necessarily’ and ‘contingently’. These can be taken both as categorematic and<br />

syncategorematic terms. If <strong>the</strong>y are taken in <strong>the</strong> first sense, <strong>the</strong>n <strong>the</strong>y determine<br />

<strong>the</strong> predicate and if <strong>the</strong>y are taken in <strong>the</strong> second sense <strong>the</strong>n <strong>the</strong>y determine <strong>the</strong><br />

composition <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> subject and <strong>the</strong> predicate, but as we just saw, if something<br />

determines <strong>the</strong> composition <strong>the</strong>n it also determines <strong>the</strong> predicate. He writes fur<strong>the</strong>r<br />

that:<br />

If necessarily’ is an adverb, <strong>the</strong>n it determines something that is an<br />

act and is in <strong>the</strong> manner <strong>of</strong> an act. But <strong>the</strong> composition belonging<br />

to <strong>the</strong> verb in a sentence is not consignified in <strong>the</strong> manner <strong>of</strong> an act;<br />

<strong>the</strong>refore an adverb does not determine it. The assumption is clear, for<br />

<strong>the</strong> thing belonging to <strong>the</strong> verb to which <strong>the</strong> composition belongs per<br />

se is signified not in <strong>the</strong> manner <strong>of</strong> a substance but in <strong>the</strong> manner <strong>of</strong> an<br />

act proceeding from <strong>the</strong> subject, while that to which <strong>the</strong> act belongs is<br />

always signified in <strong>the</strong> manner <strong>of</strong> a substance. And thus it seems that<br />

‘necessarily’ determines <strong>the</strong> predicate in <strong>the</strong> second case just as in <strong>the</strong><br />

first. 96<br />

The argument is really interesting. In <strong>the</strong> proposition ‘Socrates runs’, ‘runs’ signifies<br />

<strong>the</strong> act <strong>of</strong> running, but it consignifies <strong>the</strong> composition <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> act with <strong>the</strong><br />

96 See William <strong>of</strong> Sherwood, Introduction to <strong>Logic</strong>, 100-1.

Hooray! Your file is uploaded and ready to be published.

Saved successfully!

Ooh no, something went wrong!