22.06.2013 Views

Handbook of the History of Logic: - Fordham University Faculty

Handbook of the History of Logic: - Fordham University Faculty

Handbook of the History of Logic: - Fordham University Faculty

SHOW MORE
SHOW LESS

You also want an ePaper? Increase the reach of your titles

YUMPU automatically turns print PDFs into web optimized ePapers that Google loves.

<strong>Logic</strong> and Theories <strong>of</strong> Meaning . . . 365<br />

It can be briefly said to <strong>the</strong> question that <strong>the</strong> contention common to<br />

many opinions, i.e. that ‘as something is understood, so it is also<br />

named’, is false if this is understood precisely, because something can<br />

be signified more distinctively than it is understood. 94<br />

From this passage it is clear that, according to Scotus, naming and understanding<br />

do not always correspond to each o<strong>the</strong>r. We can name an object without having<br />

a precise understanding <strong>of</strong> it. What a name signifies is to a considerable extent<br />

dependent upon <strong>the</strong> intention <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> speaker. It does not mean that speaking<br />

occurs without understanding, but a speaker may successfully refer to an object,<br />

even if his understanding <strong>of</strong> this object is incorrect or vague.<br />

With his <strong>the</strong>ory <strong>of</strong> immediate signification <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> thing Scotus was <strong>the</strong> first to<br />

reject <strong>the</strong> parallelism between understanding and signifying, which makes <strong>the</strong> conclusion<br />

justified that he made an original contribution in <strong>the</strong> history <strong>of</strong> semantics. 95<br />

In fact, he can be seen to have found a way to account for <strong>the</strong> distinction between<br />

meaning and reference, in <strong>the</strong> sense that meaning has to do with understanding<br />

and reference with naming. Shortly after he died, philosophers like Ockham and<br />

Buridan showed that supposition taken as a property <strong>of</strong> mental terms is a much<br />

better tool to solve referential problems. 96<br />

Concrete and abstract terms<br />

In <strong>the</strong> previous paragraphs I have examined <strong>the</strong> various answers to <strong>the</strong> question<br />

‘what does a name signify’?, where <strong>the</strong> names considered were concrete general<br />

terms, like ‘man’ and ‘animal’. But in <strong>the</strong> late 13 th century many authors had a<br />

particular interest in <strong>the</strong> semantic function <strong>of</strong> o<strong>the</strong>r terms, such as abstract essential<br />

terms (for example ‘humanity’), and abstract accidental terms (for example<br />

‘whiteness’). I shall discuss <strong>the</strong> headlines <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> modistic approach to this subject<br />

in <strong>the</strong> second part <strong>of</strong> this chapter when we speak about terms <strong>of</strong> second intention,<br />

but here I shall pay attention to Scotus’ view. 97 Scotus’ rejection <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> parallel<br />

between signifying and understanding and <strong>the</strong> acceptance <strong>of</strong> signification as a<br />

direct relation between word and thing could easily lead to a <strong>the</strong>ory <strong>of</strong> strict correspondence<br />

between language and reality, so that for example <strong>the</strong> concrete term<br />

‘white’ and <strong>the</strong> abstract term ‘whiteness’ signify numerically different things. Scotus’<br />

account <strong>of</strong> concrete and abstract terms shows that this can be avoided. In<br />

short, his opinion is that <strong>the</strong> concrete term ‘white’ and <strong>the</strong> abstract term ‘whiteness’<br />

signify <strong>the</strong> same white thing, but in different ways (modes <strong>of</strong> signifying). 98<br />

94Duns Scotus, Ordinatio I, d. 22, q. un., n. 4. Cited from Pini [2001, p. 39] in his translation.<br />

95Pini [2001, p. 51].<br />

96Marmo [1983, pp. 170–4] shows that <strong>the</strong>re are some affinities between Scotus’ terminology<br />

and that <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> Oxford tradition <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> <strong>the</strong>ory <strong>of</strong> supposition.<br />

97For a thorough discussion <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> modistic approach, see: Ebbesen [1988].<br />

98Rep. Par. IV, d. 12, q.1, n. 10, In Praed., q. 8. Marmo [1983, n. 47], notices that Scotus’<br />

definition <strong>of</strong> modi significandi is different from <strong>the</strong> Modists’s. For Scotus <strong>the</strong>ir only function is<br />

<strong>the</strong> regulation <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> well-formation (congruitas) <strong>of</strong> propositions. I can add that this use <strong>of</strong> modi<br />

significandi is common even in <strong>the</strong> fourteenth century, e.g. in <strong>the</strong> work <strong>of</strong> John Buridan.

Hooray! Your file is uploaded and ready to be published.

Saved successfully!

Ooh no, something went wrong!