22.06.2013 Views

Handbook of the History of Logic: - Fordham University Faculty

Handbook of the History of Logic: - Fordham University Faculty

Handbook of the History of Logic: - Fordham University Faculty

SHOW MORE
SHOW LESS

You also want an ePaper? Increase the reach of your titles

YUMPU automatically turns print PDFs into web optimized ePapers that Google loves.

Medieval Modal Theories and Modal <strong>Logic</strong> 541<br />

32a29-b1). This was taken for granted in mid-thirteenth-century logical treatises.<br />

It was noted that while <strong>the</strong> converted propositions <strong>of</strong> indefinite contingency propositions<br />

are <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> same type <strong>of</strong> contingency, <strong>the</strong> conversion <strong>of</strong> natural contingency<br />

propositions or <strong>of</strong> those <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> minor part contingency, whe<strong>the</strong>r with respect to<br />

quality or terms, result in different modal propositions. 119 There were extensive<br />

discussions <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> kinds <strong>of</strong> contingency in <strong>the</strong> commentaries by Robert Kilwardby<br />

and Albert <strong>the</strong> Great and in o<strong>the</strong>r treatises by <strong>the</strong>ir contemporaries based on<br />

various philosophical ideas <strong>of</strong> contingency. 120 Following Aristotle’s remark in An.<br />

pr. I.13, 32b23-32, according to which ‘A contingently belongs to B’ may mean<br />

ei<strong>the</strong>r ‘to that to which B belongs’ or ‘to that to which B contingently belongs’,<br />

Kilwardby argues that <strong>the</strong> major premise in uniform first figure contingency syllogisms<br />

is read in <strong>the</strong> second way, having <strong>the</strong> form ‘Everything/something that<br />

is contingently B is contingently A’. 121 Contingency premises are ampliated, if<br />

syllogistic relations do not demand restrictions. 122 In explaining <strong>the</strong> difference<br />

between necessity propositions and contingency propositions in this respect, Kilwardby<br />

teaches that syllogistic terms are substantial or accidental. Substantial<br />

terms necessarily stand for <strong>the</strong> things <strong>the</strong>y signify, while accidental terms contingently<br />

stand for <strong>the</strong>m. Since <strong>the</strong> terms in per se necessity propositions are<br />

substantial, ‘Every A is necessarily B’ and ‘Whatever is necessarily A is necessarily<br />

B’ mean <strong>the</strong> same. 123<br />

Averroes did not have much to add to what Aristotle says about <strong>the</strong> convertibility<br />

<strong>of</strong> contingent propositions, except that <strong>the</strong> subject terms <strong>of</strong> syllogistic contingency<br />

propositions are always meant to be read with <strong>the</strong> prefix<br />

‘Everything/something which is or is contingently’. 124 As distinct from <strong>the</strong> mid-<br />

119 In Pr. an. (Orléans), 186b; Lambert <strong>of</strong> Auxerre, <strong>Logic</strong>a, 42.26-49.43; Robert Kilwardby,<br />

In Pr. An. 8rb-va; Peter <strong>of</strong> Spain, Syncategoreumata, ed. with an introduction by L.M. de<br />

Rijk, with an English translation by J. Spruyt, Studien und Texte zur Geistesgeschichte des<br />

Mittelalters 30 (Leiden: Brill, 1992), VII.6, 284-7: 17-19, 294-7; Albert <strong>the</strong> Great, Pr. an. I.13,<br />

477a-480b; 14, 482b; Roger Bacon, Summulae III.1.2, 61-6; Jacobi 1980, 83-4, 382. For <strong>the</strong> kinds<br />

<strong>of</strong> contingency, see also Averroes, Media expsitio in libros Priorun Resolutoriorum 35vb-36ra.<br />

120 According to Aristotle, universal negative possibility proper propositions are simply convertible<br />

into universal negative possibility propositions (An. pr. 1.3, 25b3-14). It was concluded<br />

from this that a universal negative contingency proposition is convertible into a universal negative<br />

possibility proposition; see Lambert <strong>of</strong> Auxerre, <strong>Logic</strong>a, 47.14-48.7; Robert Kilwardby, In<br />

Pr. an. 9ra; Roger Bacon, Summulae, III.1.2, 64; albert <strong>the</strong> Great, In Pr.an. I.14, 480a-482b.<br />

121 Kilwardby, In Pr. an. .<br />

122 In Pr. an. 19vb; 21ra-b; Kilwardby says later that <strong>the</strong> subject term <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> minor premise<br />

<strong>of</strong> a universal first-figure syllogism may also be actual (22rb).<br />

123 In In Pr. an. 21ra-b; 22ra-b. See also Thom 2007, 22-3. These considerations did not<br />

influence conversion rules. Kilwardby did not find it problematic that <strong>the</strong> contingency premises<br />

in various mixed third-figure moods, which he did not treat as ampliated, were converted in<br />

Aristotle’s modal syllogistic.<br />

124 Media expositio in libros Priorum Resolutoriorum, 38rb; 44ra-b. According to Averroes,<br />

Alfarabi mistakenly argued that <strong>the</strong> subject-term ampliates to <strong>the</strong> possible in all syllogistic<br />

premises. In fact this is true only <strong>of</strong> contingency propositions (28vb). Alfarabi’s lost commentary<br />

on <strong>the</strong> Prior Analytics may be <strong>the</strong> source <strong>of</strong> Avicenna’s view <strong>of</strong> ampliation (note 117 above).<br />

See also T. Street, “‘The Eminent Later Scholar” in Avicenna’s Book <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> Syllogism’, Arabic<br />

Science and Philosophy 11 (2001), 205-18.

Hooray! Your file is uploaded and ready to be published.

Saved successfully!

Ooh no, something went wrong!