22.06.2013 Views

Handbook of the History of Logic: - Fordham University Faculty

Handbook of the History of Logic: - Fordham University Faculty

Handbook of the History of Logic: - Fordham University Faculty

SHOW MORE
SHOW LESS

Create successful ePaper yourself

Turn your PDF publications into a flip-book with our unique Google optimized e-Paper software.

page refs<br />

page refs<br />

76 John Marenbon<br />

by no means clear though what sense is made by <strong>the</strong> views Jolivet attributes to<br />

Roscelin, or whe<strong>the</strong>r Roscelin really held <strong>the</strong>m. (See also [Tweedale, 1988, 000-<br />

000]). Ano<strong>the</strong>r opponent <strong>of</strong> realism was immediately recognized in Gerlandus<br />

(though his work was wrongly place in <strong>the</strong> eleventh century: see §4 above). In <strong>the</strong><br />

preface to his edition <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> Dialectica, perhaps still <strong>the</strong> best analysis <strong>of</strong> Gerlandus’s<br />

position, De Rijk notes what he calls his ‘problemless nominalism’ [Gerlandus,<br />

1959, liii-lv; Tweedale, 1988, 000-000]. Gerlandus clearly hopes to interpret <strong>the</strong><br />

Isagoge and Categories as discussions about utterances (voces), and yet <strong>the</strong>re is no<br />

explicit sign <strong>of</strong> argument for a metaphysical position (such as that <strong>the</strong>re exist only<br />

particulars), and his semantics remains unclear, because some <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> most difficult<br />

and revealing passages in <strong>the</strong> Dialectica have not yet been properly explained.<br />

Recently, an ambitious attempt has been made by Yukio Iwakuma to bring<br />

toge<strong>the</strong>r what is known about Roscelin and Gerlandus, with some anonymous<br />

material he has discovered and <strong>the</strong> chronicle accounts (see above, §6) into an<br />

account <strong>of</strong> ‘vocalism’ or ‘pre-vocalism’ (<strong>the</strong> term derives from <strong>the</strong> Latin vocales,<br />

used in <strong>the</strong> early twelfth century to describe Abelard and those who followed<br />

his position on universals) [Iwakuma, 1992]. The chronicles, he believes, name<br />

<strong>the</strong> main protagonists: John (o<strong>the</strong>rwise unknown); his pupils – Roscelin, Arnulf<br />

<strong>of</strong> Laon and Robert <strong>of</strong> Paris. To <strong>the</strong>se he adds Gerlandus, now recognized as<br />

Gerlandus <strong>of</strong> Besançon. All <strong>the</strong> literal commentaries listed in §3 above (except for<br />

P6, C6 and H7, on which he has not written) are linked by him to this movement.<br />

Constant Mews at one stage suggested that <strong>the</strong> Priscian Glosulae might belong<br />

to it too, and that <strong>the</strong>ir original author was <strong>the</strong> John mentioned in <strong>the</strong> chronicles;<br />

but his view has not found much support [Mews, 1992, 14, 33; cf. Mews, 1998, 50<br />

— 55, and cf. 68- 73].<br />

I contributed to this discussion [Marenbon, 1997b, 108-113; 2004, 26-34] by<br />

linking <strong>the</strong> supposed early commentaries by Abelard (P5, H4, D7) with <strong>the</strong> movement<br />

identified by Iwakuma. I also insisted that this group <strong>of</strong> early ‘vocalists’<br />

identified by Iwakuma (including <strong>the</strong> young Abelard) needed to be distinguished<br />

sharply from Abelard and <strong>the</strong> vocalists who were his school. The mature Abelard,<br />

I said, had a very definite metaphysical position: that only particular substances<br />

and accidents exist. The earlier group <strong>of</strong> logicians, and Abelard c. 1100-5, were,<br />

by contrast just following an exegetical strategy — that <strong>of</strong> reading <strong>the</strong> texts <strong>of</strong><br />

Aristotle, Porphyry and Boethius in voce, that is to say, taking <strong>the</strong> words <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong><br />

text to refer to o<strong>the</strong>r voces, not to things. That <strong>the</strong>y read <strong>the</strong> texts in this fashion<br />

did not mean that <strong>the</strong>y must have believed that <strong>the</strong>re are no things which correspond<br />

to <strong>the</strong> words; for, as I pointed out, even mentions <strong>of</strong> individual substances<br />

and accidents in <strong>the</strong> texts were read as referring to words. Iwakuma now accepts<br />

this qualification <strong>of</strong> his position, and distinguishes between ‘proto-vocalists’ (at<br />

<strong>the</strong> turn <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> twelfth century) and ‘vocalists’ (Peter Abelard and h is followers)<br />

[Iwakuma, Forthcoming-B].<br />

My view, however, obscures as much as it reveals. Although it is true that<br />

explaining <strong>the</strong> logical texts was <strong>the</strong> priority for <strong>the</strong>se teachers, and that it is important<br />

not to wish on <strong>the</strong>m a metaphysical position, <strong>the</strong> idea that <strong>the</strong>y were

Hooray! Your file is uploaded and ready to be published.

Saved successfully!

Ooh no, something went wrong!