22.06.2013 Views

Handbook of the History of Logic: - Fordham University Faculty

Handbook of the History of Logic: - Fordham University Faculty

Handbook of the History of Logic: - Fordham University Faculty

SHOW MORE
SHOW LESS

Create successful ePaper yourself

Turn your PDF publications into a flip-book with our unique Google optimized e-Paper software.

54 John Marenbon<br />

(for w) as a word for ano<strong>the</strong>r word (as a word for ‘w’), but only where ‘w’ signifies<br />

w, not where it merely appellates w. He gives as an example a passage in <strong>the</strong><br />

Categories where Aristotle says ‘every substance seems to signify this something’,<br />

where by ‘substance’ Aristotle must have meant ‘substance word’. The implication<br />

is that, for Anselm, on <strong>the</strong> Aristotelian reading, <strong>the</strong> question about denominatives<br />

should not really be considered to be one about things at all. The claim that<br />

‘Grammaticus is a quality’ must be taken as ‘The word ‘grammaticus’ signifies a<br />

quality’ (i.e. as 22, which has already been established). Were a similar analysis,<br />

taking <strong>the</strong> word to refer to ano<strong>the</strong>r word, applicable to <strong>the</strong> claim ‘grammaticus is a<br />

substance’, it would come out as ‘The word ‘grammaticus’ appellates a substance’,<br />

that is, as 23). But Aristotle does not accept this analysis for propositions where<br />

<strong>the</strong> relation is one <strong>of</strong> appellation, not signification, and so <strong>the</strong>re is no acceptable<br />

meaning that can be given to ‘grammaticus is a substance’.<br />

Anselm is, <strong>the</strong>refore, presenting what he recognizes as a narrowly Aristotelian<br />

solution to his problem, and <strong>the</strong> student in <strong>the</strong> dialogue expresses this limitation<br />

when he sums up <strong>the</strong> reply as being ‘according to Aristotle’s treatise and according<br />

to his followers.’ It is interesting to recognize that, earlier in <strong>the</strong> treatise, Anselm<br />

had presented a different solution to <strong>the</strong> initial problem, which seems a little more<br />

broadly based:<br />

M. Tell me, when you speak to me about a grammaticus, what should I understand<br />

you to be talking about — <strong>the</strong> word ‘grammaticus’, or <strong>the</strong> things it<br />

signifies?<br />

P. The things.<br />

M. What things, <strong>the</strong>n, does it signify?<br />

P. A man and knowledge about grammar<br />

M. So when I hear <strong>the</strong> word ‘grammaticus’, I may understand a man or knowledge<br />

about grammar, and when I am speaking about a grammaticus, Imay<br />

be speaking about a man or knowledge about grammar.<br />

P. So it must be.<br />

M. Tell me <strong>the</strong>n, is a man a substance, or is it in a subject?<br />

P. It’s a substance, not something in a subject.<br />

M. Is knowledge about grammar a quality and in a subject?<br />

P. It’s both.<br />

M. Why <strong>the</strong>n is it strange if someone says that grammaticus is a substance<br />

and not in a subject with respect to a man (secundum hominem) and that<br />

grammaticus is a quality and in a subject with respect to knowledge about<br />

grammar (secundum grammaticam)? [Anselm, 1946, 1, 154:7-21]

Hooray! Your file is uploaded and ready to be published.

Saved successfully!

Ooh no, something went wrong!