22.06.2013 Views

Handbook of the History of Logic: - Fordham University Faculty

Handbook of the History of Logic: - Fordham University Faculty

Handbook of the History of Logic: - Fordham University Faculty

SHOW MORE
SHOW LESS

Create successful ePaper yourself

Turn your PDF publications into a flip-book with our unique Google optimized e-Paper software.

18 John Marenbon<br />

inherited, trying to think about <strong>the</strong> meaning <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong>se Stoic-derived formulas, but<br />

within <strong>the</strong> context <strong>of</strong> his own term-logic.<br />

The strange character <strong>of</strong> Boethius’s hypo<strong>the</strong>tical syllogistic comes out even more<br />

clearly when he treats <strong>the</strong> negation <strong>of</strong> a conditional in On Hypo<strong>the</strong>tical Syllogisms.<br />

Not realizing that his discussions should be construed as term logic, earlier commentators<br />

[Dürr, 1951; Kneale and Kneale, 1975, 191; Barnes, 1981, 83; cf. Martin,<br />

1991, 295-6] argued that Boethius thought <strong>the</strong> contradictory negation <strong>of</strong> ‘If p, <strong>the</strong>n<br />

q’ is‘Ifp, <strong>the</strong>n not-q’, ra<strong>the</strong>r than ‘Not (If p, <strong>the</strong>n q)’ as in classical propositional<br />

calculus. Therefore, <strong>the</strong>y concluded, he had a strange propositional system. But,<br />

as Martin puts it [1991, 279]: ‘The problem is not . . . that Boethius’ logic is not<br />

classical propositional calculus but ra<strong>the</strong>r it is not propositional at all.’ Boethius<br />

is in fact both much less strange in his underlying conception than he has been seen<br />

to be, and yet at <strong>the</strong> same time more distant from contemporary logical models.<br />

Boethius’s account <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> state <strong>of</strong> affairs that must be <strong>the</strong> case for a conditional to<br />

be ‘negated’ or ‘destroyed’ is exactly <strong>the</strong> same as <strong>the</strong> contemporary logician’s account<br />

<strong>of</strong> what obtains when a whole conditional is negated, but Boethius can only<br />

<strong>of</strong>fer his explanation, however tortuously, using term logic. For <strong>the</strong> conditional ‘If<br />

A is, B is’ to be destroyed, we must show ‘not that A is not or B is not, but that,<br />

when A is posited, it does not immediately follow that B is, but that A can be<br />

even if <strong>the</strong> term B is not’ (I.9.7). And even in his extended discussion <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> valid<br />

forms <strong>of</strong> hypo<strong>the</strong>tical syllogisms, Boethius seems, whilst always working in term<br />

logic, to be mimicking <strong>the</strong> results which would obtain in a propositional calculus,<br />

<strong>of</strong>ten employing various extra premisses that allow him to reach <strong>the</strong> results which,<br />

by means <strong>of</strong> examples, he has identified as <strong>the</strong> correct ones (cf. [Marenbon, 2003,<br />

53-55, 191]).<br />

Boethius and Topical Argument ([Green-Pedersen, 1984, 37-81])<br />

The remaining logical monograph by Boethius, On Topical differentiae (De topicis<br />

differentiis) (TD) [Boethius, 1990, 1-92; trsl. Boethius, 1978; Boethius, 1891,<br />

1173-1216] was written near <strong>the</strong> end <strong>of</strong> his life (c. 522-3), at a time when topical<br />

argument became a central concern for him. Shortly before, he had written a<br />

commentary on Cicero’s Topics (TC) [Boethius, 1833; transl. Boethius, 1988]<br />

that is closely related to it, translated Aristotle’s Topics into Latin, and probably<br />

written a commentary on it, now lost.<br />

Much as in <strong>the</strong> case <strong>of</strong> hypo<strong>the</strong>tical syllogistic, Boethius’ work is <strong>the</strong> only substantial<br />

survival from <strong>the</strong> late ancient tradition <strong>of</strong> topical argument as it had<br />

developed after <strong>the</strong> time <strong>of</strong> Cicero. One <strong>of</strong> its principle exponents had been <strong>the</strong><br />

fourth-century Peripatetic philosopher, Themistius. He and Cicero are Boethius’s<br />

special authorities, and one <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> main aims <strong>of</strong> TD is to compare <strong>the</strong> apparently<br />

different lists <strong>of</strong> topical differentiae given by <strong>the</strong>se two philosophers, showing that<br />

<strong>the</strong>y really coincide.<br />

In <strong>the</strong> way it is structured around a list <strong>of</strong> topical differentiae, <strong>the</strong> topical <strong>the</strong>ory<br />

Boethius presents clearly descends from Cicero, though Cicero had just called <strong>the</strong>m<br />

‘topics’. Discussion <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> topics is no longer, however, <strong>the</strong> mixture <strong>of</strong> law and

Hooray! Your file is uploaded and ready to be published.

Saved successfully!

Ooh no, something went wrong!