22.06.2013 Views

Handbook of the History of Logic: - Fordham University Faculty

Handbook of the History of Logic: - Fordham University Faculty

Handbook of the History of Logic: - Fordham University Faculty

SHOW MORE
SHOW LESS

You also want an ePaper? Increase the reach of your titles

YUMPU automatically turns print PDFs into web optimized ePapers that Google loves.

656 Petr Dvoˇrák<br />

that <strong>of</strong> arectisadobliqua(from terms in <strong>the</strong> nominative to oblique terms), but regarded<br />

it as a type <strong>of</strong> non-syllogistic immediate inference. 33 A step fur<strong>the</strong>r would<br />

be to say that <strong>the</strong> standard upright form is a special case <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> oblique form;<br />

hence, really, <strong>the</strong> oblique form is paradigmatic for any statement. We shall see<br />

below that this is arguably <strong>the</strong> path Caramuel will eventually take.<br />

There seem to be two possible ways <strong>of</strong> analyzing a relational statement, for<br />

instance “every man commits some sin”:<br />

every man is [some sin is committed by]<br />

The first way regards <strong>the</strong> complex predicate consisting <strong>of</strong> a verb and an oblique<br />

term to be an embedded predication; hence <strong>the</strong> oblique term is regarded to be<br />

a (subordinate) logical subject. Hence, <strong>the</strong>re are two subject-predicate structures<br />

present within a relational statement and, consequently, two copulae. This<br />

ra<strong>the</strong>r conservative view <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> logical form <strong>of</strong> a relational statement accommodates<br />

<strong>the</strong> latter statements within a quantifier-subject-copula-predicate upright<br />

scheme, without reducing <strong>the</strong>m to this form altoge<strong>the</strong>r. (The relational form is<br />

clearly seen as different from <strong>the</strong> non-relational one, but not substantially, as one<br />

can see). Caramuel takes this approach in his initial formal symbolism introduced<br />

to grasp <strong>the</strong> logical form <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> relational statement. Apart from <strong>the</strong> signs for<br />

quantifiers “a”, “i”, “e” (all, some, no), <strong>the</strong> asterisk symbol * divides <strong>the</strong> subject<br />

part from <strong>the</strong> predicate part. For instance, “a*i” means (every...is some..., e.g.<br />

“every man commits some sin”). The introduction, however, <strong>of</strong> two symbols for<br />

negation, copula negation “ñ” and quantifier negation “n”, and <strong>the</strong>ir possible positions<br />

in Caramuel show that Caramuel assumes <strong>the</strong>re are two copulae in relational<br />

statements. The following are <strong>the</strong> possible places <strong>of</strong> negation:<br />

(i) n-*-<br />

(ii) -ñ*-<br />

(iii) -*n-<br />

(iv) -*ñ-<br />

33For example: A circle is a plane figure. Therefore, whoever draws a circle draws a plane<br />

figure.<br />

J. Jungius (Junge), <strong>Logic</strong>a Hamburgensis, hoc est, Institutiones <strong>Logic</strong>ae In usum Schol. Hamburgensis<br />

conscriptae, et sex libris comprehensae, ed. R. W. Meyer — J. J. Augustin, Hamburg<br />

1957 (1st edition 1638), Lib. II, c. 4, § 6; Lib. III, c. 1. § 5. For <strong>the</strong> logic <strong>of</strong> relations in Jungius<br />

cf. e.g. Ashworth [1967] and Dvo˘rák [2006].<br />

Caramuel also suggests <strong>the</strong> reduction <strong>of</strong> oblique forms into upright ones, but more for <strong>the</strong> sake<br />

<strong>of</strong> showing <strong>the</strong> usefulness <strong>of</strong> his new system, ra<strong>the</strong>r than as a necessary procedure to exhibit <strong>the</strong><br />

true form disguised or clouded by <strong>the</strong> oblique form, as in Jungius. Cf. Ibid., Lib. II, c. 16, § 1:<br />

Crypsis est affectio Syllogismi oratione externa propositi, qua ejus forma ita occultatur, ut cum<br />

sit legitimus, talis tamen non esse videatur (“Disguise is a property <strong>of</strong> a syllogism put forth in<br />

an external linguistic formulation, in which its form is so hidden that in spite <strong>of</strong> being valid, it<br />

does not appear so”).

Hooray! Your file is uploaded and ready to be published.

Saved successfully!

Ooh no, something went wrong!