22.06.2013 Views

Handbook of the History of Logic: - Fordham University Faculty

Handbook of the History of Logic: - Fordham University Faculty

Handbook of the History of Logic: - Fordham University Faculty

SHOW MORE
SHOW LESS

Create successful ePaper yourself

Turn your PDF publications into a flip-book with our unique Google optimized e-Paper software.

612 E. Jennifer Ashworth<br />

what we find is glossed texts, that is, texts with marginal notes, some <strong>of</strong> a very<br />

simple nature, and some very lengthy and elaborate. 13 By <strong>the</strong> mid-thirteenth<br />

century, <strong>the</strong> fully-fledged commentary had come to dominate, and during <strong>the</strong> thirteenth<br />

and fourteenth centuries all <strong>the</strong> great names in philosophy such as Albert<br />

<strong>the</strong> Great, Thomas Aquinas, John Duns Scotus and William <strong>of</strong> Ockham, wrote<br />

commentaries on at least some <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> books <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> Organon. There were two main<br />

types <strong>of</strong> commentary. 14 First, <strong>the</strong>re is <strong>the</strong> literal commentary, typified by those<br />

<strong>of</strong> Aquinas. The author <strong>of</strong> a literal commentary divided <strong>the</strong> work into a series <strong>of</strong><br />

lectiones, and <strong>the</strong>n treated it passage by passage. A paraphrase would be <strong>of</strong>fered,<br />

toge<strong>the</strong>r with an explanation <strong>of</strong> difficult or important phrases, and points <strong>of</strong> doctrine<br />

would be investigated. Especially in <strong>the</strong> later middle ages, dubia were <strong>of</strong>ten<br />

added and discussed at some length. Second, <strong>the</strong>re is <strong>the</strong> question-commentary,<br />

whose author did not divide or paraphrase <strong>the</strong> text, but instead considered a<br />

series <strong>of</strong> questions which arose from points in <strong>the</strong> text. During <strong>the</strong> fifteenth century<br />

<strong>the</strong> distinction between <strong>the</strong> two types <strong>of</strong> commentary became blurred, and<br />

we find question-commentaries which contain paraphrases, and literal commentaries<br />

which contain dubia whose length and structure allies <strong>the</strong>m to <strong>the</strong> quaestio.<br />

Moreover, literal commentaries ceased to be divided into lectiones, instead being<br />

organized in accordance with <strong>the</strong> accepted division <strong>of</strong> Aristotle’s text into chapters<br />

and tractates. 15 The Coimbra commentary <strong>of</strong> 1606 is an excellent example<br />

<strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> hybrid question-commentary with its chapter divisions, chapter summaries,<br />

textual commentary and lengthy quaestiones.<br />

The Coimbra commentary illustrates ano<strong>the</strong>r trend which became important in<br />

<strong>the</strong> fifteenth century, that towards commentaries on <strong>the</strong> entire Organon. 16 Indeed,<br />

<strong>the</strong> very name Organon when used as a title ra<strong>the</strong>r than a description seems to be<br />

a late fifteenth-century innovation. Commentaries on individual books continued<br />

to be written; but <strong>the</strong> fifteenth-century Thomists at <strong>the</strong> Bursa Montis in Cologne<br />

produced a single commentary on <strong>the</strong> <strong>Logic</strong>a vetus and ano<strong>the</strong>r on <strong>the</strong> <strong>Logic</strong>a<br />

nova, as did Johannes Versor in Paris. 17 Also at Paris we find George <strong>of</strong> Brussels<br />

and Pierre Tartaret, whose respective commentaries on <strong>the</strong> entire Organon were<br />

first published in 1493, and enjoyed considerable success during <strong>the</strong> first decades<br />

<strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> sixteenth century. Later sixteenth-century commentaries included that by<br />

Authors,” ibid., 30 (1974), 119–144. For a listing <strong>of</strong> Aristotle commentaries in <strong>the</strong> period 1500–<br />

1650, see C. H. Lohr, Latin Aristotle Commentaries. II. Renaissance Authors, Firenze: Leo S.<br />

Olschki, 1988. See also C. H. Lohr, “Renaissance Latin Aristotle Commentaries: Authors A-B,”<br />

Studies in <strong>the</strong> Renaissance 21 (1974), 228–289; “Authors C,” Renaissance Quarterly, 28 (1975),<br />

689–741; “Authors D-F,” ibid., 29 (1976), 714–745; “Authors G-K,” ibid., 30 (1977), 681–741;<br />

“Authors L-M,” ibid., 31 (1978), 532–603; “Authors N-Ph,” ibid., 32 (1979), 529–580; “Authors<br />

Pi-Sm,” ibid., 33 (1980), 623–734; “Authors So-Z,” ibid., 35 (1982), 164–256.<br />

13 Dod, “Aristoteles latinus”, pp. 73–74.<br />

14 Green-Pedersen, The Tradition <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> Topics, pp. 88–89, distinguishes three.<br />

15 Green-Pedersen, The Tradition <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> Topics, p. 91.<br />

16 For comment, see Lohr, “Renaissance Latin Aristotle Commentaries: Authors A-B”, pp.<br />

230–231 or Lohr, Latin Aristotle Commentaries II, p.XIV.<br />

17 For publication details, see W. R. Risse, Bibliographia <strong>Logic</strong>a Band I. 1472–1800<br />

(Hildesheim: Georg Olms, 1965).

Hooray! Your file is uploaded and ready to be published.

Saved successfully!

Ooh no, something went wrong!