22.06.2013 Views

Handbook of the History of Logic: - Fordham University Faculty

Handbook of the History of Logic: - Fordham University Faculty

Handbook of the History of Logic: - Fordham University Faculty

SHOW MORE
SHOW LESS

Create successful ePaper yourself

Turn your PDF publications into a flip-book with our unique Google optimized e-Paper software.

Peter Abelard and His Contemporaries 147<br />

more than to assert, with respect to a given proposition, that things really are as<br />

it says <strong>the</strong>y are. This view bears obvious similarities to Abelard’s own account<br />

<strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> dictum. The associated account <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> true and <strong>the</strong> false is comparable to<br />

what is now labelled as a “deflationary” approach. 111<br />

(iv) This brings us to <strong>the</strong> remaining view, which is likely that <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> Melidunenses<br />

<strong>the</strong>mselves, given that it is presented approvingly [Iwakuma, 1997, p. 21]. It has<br />

a great deal more in common with <strong>the</strong> view <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> Porretani, in ascribing to <strong>the</strong><br />

enuntiabile a reality outside <strong>the</strong> mind at <strong>the</strong> cost <strong>of</strong> having to articulate a metaphysically<br />

complex view. And like <strong>the</strong> Porretani, <strong>the</strong>Melidunenses do not tend<br />

to be metaphysically reductionist. In fact on this matter <strong>the</strong>ir proposal is more<br />

metaphysically complex. The Porretani start with familiar items — objects and<br />

properties — and envisage compositions <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong>m to get <strong>the</strong>ir enuntiabile. But<br />

Melidunenses get <strong>the</strong>irs by envisaging an item entirely distinct from <strong>the</strong> world<br />

<strong>of</strong> objects and properties, accessible only to reason, and not to <strong>the</strong> senses, and<br />

accordingly <strong>the</strong>y confer special metaphysical status upon <strong>the</strong> enuntiabile. Indeed,<br />

this entity falls right outside <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> Aristotelian categories, and tends to be characterizable<br />

more in terms <strong>of</strong> what it is not than what it is. It is, in particular, not<br />

tied to particularities <strong>of</strong> linguistic formulation, so that <strong>the</strong> propositions Marcus<br />

est albus and Tullius est candidus both give us <strong>the</strong> same enuntiabile (that Cicero<br />

is white) [Nuchelmans, 1973, p. 172]. 112 In <strong>the</strong> end, this proposal explains how<br />

enuntiabilia can serve as <strong>the</strong> cause <strong>of</strong> truth, but is as much in need <strong>of</strong> additional<br />

clarification as Abelard’s proposal, and probably more in need <strong>of</strong> it than that <strong>of</strong><br />

<strong>the</strong> Montani and <strong>the</strong> Porretani.<br />

However one explains it, having a notion <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> dictum/enuntiabile provides<br />

a new avenue for explaining, in <strong>the</strong> most general sense, what an argument is.<br />

Abelard is inclined to view <strong>the</strong> argument as being nothing but <strong>the</strong> meaningful<br />

words <strong>of</strong> which it is composed — in particular, <strong>the</strong> words constituting <strong>the</strong> premise<br />

or premises (<strong>the</strong> conclusion being that which awaits pro<strong>of</strong>, and <strong>the</strong> premise or<br />

premises being that which supplies it). But this seemingly uncontroversial view<br />

does actually occasion some controversy, and <strong>the</strong> dictum/enuntiabile, notwithstanding<br />

its source in Abelard’s own writings, is appealed to on this issue as a<br />

means <strong>of</strong> staking out different positions. All <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> schools register dissent from<br />

Abelard’s view. One <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> reasons for this dissent, apparently, lies in <strong>the</strong> conventional<br />

status <strong>of</strong> human language, every sound or written character <strong>of</strong> which could<br />

have been established in a different signification than it was [Iwakuma, 2004, p.<br />

319]. How <strong>the</strong>n are propositions able to be stand in a relation <strong>of</strong> binding inferential<br />

linkage? It is tempting to say that what is binding in an argument’s inferential<br />

linkage is to be found in <strong>the</strong> dicta/enuntiabilia corresponding to its constituent<br />

propositions.<br />

111 [Kneepkens, 1997, pp. 85-86] discusses Parvipontanian views about <strong>the</strong> enuntiabile in connection<br />

with a later figure from this school (Alexander Nequam). [Iwakuma, 1997, p. 21] associates<br />

this passage from <strong>the</strong> Ars Meliduna with <strong>the</strong> Parvipontanian school based on similarities<br />

<strong>of</strong> content.<br />

112 See also [Martin, 1997b].

Hooray! Your file is uploaded and ready to be published.

Saved successfully!

Ooh no, something went wrong!