22.06.2013 Views

Handbook of the History of Logic: - Fordham University Faculty

Handbook of the History of Logic: - Fordham University Faculty

Handbook of the History of Logic: - Fordham University Faculty

SHOW MORE
SHOW LESS

Create successful ePaper yourself

Turn your PDF publications into a flip-book with our unique Google optimized e-Paper software.

672 Russell Wahl<br />

an obscure judgement <strong>the</strong>y make concerning <strong>the</strong> nature <strong>of</strong> something which <strong>the</strong>y<br />

think exists in <strong>the</strong> painful spot and which <strong>the</strong>y suppose to resemble <strong>the</strong> sensation<br />

<strong>of</strong> pain; but in fact it is <strong>the</strong> sensation alone which <strong>the</strong>y perceive clearly” [Adam<br />

and Tannery, 1964-76, VIII-1, 22; Cottingham et al., 1985-1991, I, 208]. Descartes<br />

is known for saying that extension and motion are contained clearly in <strong>the</strong> idea <strong>of</strong><br />

material substance, but that heat, color, etc. are not so contained. An idea (or<br />

perception) <strong>of</strong> material things which included extension and motion, but didn’t<br />

clearly exclude <strong>the</strong>se o<strong>the</strong>r things would be clear but not distinct. One which only<br />

included extension and motion would be clear and distinct. After giving a close<br />

approximation to Descartes’ own account <strong>of</strong> clarity and distinctness, Arnauld and<br />

Nicole added that <strong>the</strong> obscurity <strong>of</strong> ideas arises from <strong>the</strong>ir confusion, so in <strong>the</strong> end,<br />

<strong>the</strong>y take clarity and distinctness to be <strong>the</strong> same thing (70). With respect to<br />

Descartes’ example <strong>of</strong> an idea <strong>of</strong> pain being clear but not distinct, <strong>the</strong>y say that<br />

<strong>the</strong> sensation itself is both clear and distinct. “That <strong>the</strong> sensation is in <strong>the</strong> hand”,<br />

which was what was not distinct, is also, <strong>the</strong>y said, not clear (70). The obscurity is<br />

a result <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> confusion. So what we are concerned with in clarifying ideas really<br />

involves making <strong>the</strong>m distinct. In retrospect this was also Descartes’ concern.<br />

Given Arnauld’s view <strong>of</strong> an idea as <strong>the</strong> mental awareness or perception <strong>of</strong> a<br />

thing, it is <strong>the</strong> perceiving that is clear or obscure, not what is perceived. This<br />

point is sometimes overlooked, as Arnauld and Nicole occasionally classify ideas<br />

as clear and distinct simply with respect to <strong>the</strong>ir objects. Thus <strong>the</strong>y say that “<strong>the</strong><br />

idea each person has <strong>of</strong> himself as a thing that thinks is very clear, and similarly<br />

<strong>the</strong> ideas <strong>of</strong> everything dependent on our thought, such as judging, reasoning,<br />

doubting ...” (70-1) Presumably <strong>the</strong> suggestion is that when someone is thinking<br />

<strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong>se things, <strong>the</strong>se ideas are clear because what is contained in <strong>the</strong>m will strike<br />

<strong>the</strong> person having <strong>the</strong>m forcefully. Similarly <strong>the</strong>y say that “confused and obscure<br />

ideas are those we have <strong>of</strong> sensible qualities such as colors, sounds, odors, tastes,<br />

cold, hot, weight ...” (71). Properly speaking whe<strong>the</strong>r <strong>the</strong>se ideas are confused<br />

or clear would be relative to <strong>the</strong> conceiver. Given that <strong>the</strong>y said <strong>the</strong> idea <strong>of</strong> pain<br />

confined to <strong>the</strong> sensation is clear and distinct, it seems possible to have a clear idea<br />

<strong>of</strong> sensible qualities, provided any bodily location is excluded from <strong>the</strong>m. Similarly,<br />

ideas <strong>of</strong> external objects can become less obscure by reflection. Descartes himself<br />

speaks <strong>of</strong> a confused idea <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> sun and also a clearer one.<br />

Arnauld and Nicole make a distinction between <strong>the</strong> comprehension <strong>of</strong> an idea<br />

and its extension. This distinction, roughly corresponding to <strong>the</strong> present distinction<br />

between intension and extension, is important for <strong>the</strong> analyses <strong>of</strong> propositions<br />

and syllogisms given in Parts II and III. The comprehension <strong>of</strong> an idea consists<br />

<strong>of</strong> “<strong>the</strong> attributes that it contains in itself, and that cannot be removed from it<br />

without destroying it ...” (59). Those features that Descartes would have said<br />

are contained objectively in <strong>the</strong> idea will be included in this comprehension. For<br />

example, <strong>the</strong> comprehension <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> idea <strong>of</strong> a triangle will contain extension, shape,<br />

three lines, three angles, and <strong>the</strong> equality <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong>se three angles to two right angles.<br />

The extension <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> idea are “<strong>the</strong> subjects to which <strong>the</strong> idea applies” (59). These<br />

include <strong>the</strong> lower species as well as <strong>the</strong> individuals. While some have seen this

Hooray! Your file is uploaded and ready to be published.

Saved successfully!

Ooh no, something went wrong!