22.06.2013 Views

Handbook of the History of Logic: - Fordham University Faculty

Handbook of the History of Logic: - Fordham University Faculty

Handbook of the History of Logic: - Fordham University Faculty

SHOW MORE
SHOW LESS

You also want an ePaper? Increase the reach of your titles

YUMPU automatically turns print PDFs into web optimized ePapers that Google loves.

370 Ria van der Lecq<br />

that is not <strong>the</strong> result <strong>of</strong> this imposition. Fur<strong>the</strong>rmore, he rejected <strong>the</strong> notion <strong>of</strong><br />

a common ratio, with <strong>the</strong> result that <strong>the</strong>re is, in his view, no room for analogical<br />

predication <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> first and second type. The first type <strong>of</strong> analogy –Scotus uses<br />

‘cause, ‘end’ and ‘principle’ as examples – really involves univocal predication.<br />

Terms like ‘being’, as applied to substance and accident, are really equivocal.<br />

Terms belonging to <strong>the</strong> third type are really univocal. For example, ‘healthy’ is<br />

a univocal term, because it only signifies health: in <strong>the</strong> animal as in a subject, in<br />

urine as in a sign and in diet as in a conserving agent. 121 Thus, from a logical<br />

point <strong>of</strong> view <strong>the</strong>re is no need for something in between univocal and equivocal<br />

predication. In one <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> previous paragraphs we saw that Scotus rejected <strong>the</strong><br />

parallel between understanding and signifying. Now it is clear that he also rejected<br />

<strong>the</strong> strict correspondence between language and reality.<br />

PART II: THE LOGIC OF INTENTIONS<br />

Second intentions: <strong>the</strong> primary subject <strong>of</strong> logic<br />

The second half <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> 13 th century is characterized by <strong>the</strong> rise <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> <strong>the</strong>ory <strong>of</strong><br />

second intentions as <strong>the</strong> primary subject <strong>of</strong> logic. Second intentions are concepts<br />

<strong>of</strong> a certain kind, which give logic its status as a science, because <strong>the</strong>y are supposed<br />

to be universal and objective, as will be explained below. All <strong>the</strong> authors writing<br />

in this period regard second intentions as mental entities, which somehow have a<br />

foundation in reality (fundamentum in re), but <strong>the</strong> way <strong>the</strong>y see this foundation<br />

differs. They agree, however, that one should distinguish between <strong>the</strong> mental<br />

existence <strong>of</strong> a concept, which is studied by psychology, and its content, which is<br />

<strong>the</strong> proper subject <strong>of</strong> logic. 122<br />

Examples <strong>of</strong> terms signifying second intentions are ‘universal’, ‘genus’, ‘species’,<br />

‘proposition’, and ‘syllogism’. Some authors, Thomas Aquinas for example, consider<br />

second intentions as second order concepts, representing not things but o<strong>the</strong>r<br />

concepts, but o<strong>the</strong>r authors, e.g. Simon <strong>of</strong> Faversham and Radulphus Brito, assume<br />

that second intentions are representations <strong>of</strong> things as related to o<strong>the</strong>r things<br />

and that <strong>the</strong>y are founded upon special properties <strong>of</strong> extra-mental objects. Finally,<br />

Duns Scotus, Hervaeus Natalis and Peter Aureol ascribe to second intentions a special<br />

kind <strong>of</strong> being: objective being, to be distinguished from material being on <strong>the</strong><br />

one hand and purely mental being on <strong>the</strong> o<strong>the</strong>r. As we shall see below, <strong>the</strong> answer<br />

to <strong>the</strong> question: what do second intentions represent, is related to epistemological<br />

and ontological issues. But first we need to understand what an intention is.<br />

When I think, I think about something: a book, a child, my holidays last<br />

summer, my future plans etc. Sometimes it is clear what <strong>the</strong> thing is I am thinking<br />

about, sometimes it is not, but in any case my intellectual act is intentional, i.e. it<br />

is directed to something. One might even say that <strong>the</strong>re is a relationship between<br />

121For references and more details especially concerning Aquinas, see: Ashworth [1992, pp.<br />

121–131].<br />

122Pini [2002, p. 13].

Hooray! Your file is uploaded and ready to be published.

Saved successfully!

Ooh no, something went wrong!