22.06.2013 Views

Handbook of the History of Logic: - Fordham University Faculty

Handbook of the History of Logic: - Fordham University Faculty

Handbook of the History of Logic: - Fordham University Faculty

SHOW MORE
SHOW LESS

You also want an ePaper? Increase the reach of your titles

YUMPU automatically turns print PDFs into web optimized ePapers that Google loves.

474 Catarina Dutilh Novaes<br />

more so, <strong>the</strong> formal vs. material distinction that are crucial for <strong>the</strong> understanding<br />

<strong>of</strong> 14 th century <strong>the</strong>ories <strong>of</strong> consequence. Besides <strong>the</strong>se, <strong>the</strong>re is also a distinction<br />

that is sometimes found explicitly stated but sometimes not, and which sometimes<br />

overlaps with <strong>the</strong> formal vs. material distinction but sometimes does not, namely<br />

<strong>the</strong> distinction bona de forma vs. bona de materia.<br />

It is important to understand that <strong>the</strong>se divisions are not necessarily meant to<br />

be sub-divisions <strong>of</strong> each ano<strong>the</strong>r; <strong>the</strong>y are also <strong>of</strong>ten understood as alternative,<br />

overlapping ways <strong>of</strong> dividing consequences. Ockham, for example, presents several<br />

such distinctions but does not present <strong>the</strong>m as sub-divisions <strong>of</strong> one ano<strong>the</strong>r<br />

(Summa III-3, Chapter 1). So let us now take a closer look at each <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong>m.<br />

Formal vs. material consequences. This distinction first appears in Ockham<br />

(cf. [Green-Pedersen, 1984, 287]), but afterwards it is to be found in virtually all<br />

treatises on consequence in <strong>the</strong> 14 th century. However, what distinguished formal<br />

from material consequences varies per author.<br />

For Ockham, this distinction is related to his doctrine <strong>of</strong> intrinsic and extrinsic<br />

middles. Ockham says that a consequence is formal when <strong>the</strong>re is such middle,<br />

intrinsic or extrinsic, validating <strong>the</strong> consequence; o<strong>the</strong>rwise, when <strong>the</strong>re isn’t such<br />

middle and <strong>the</strong> consequence holds only in virtue <strong>of</strong> its very terms (Summa <strong>Logic</strong>ae,<br />

p. 589), it is a material consequence. As already mentioned, Ockham’s extrinsic<br />

and intrinsic middles are reminiscent <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> topical framework, but <strong>the</strong>y are extremely<br />

modified versions <strong>of</strong> topical concepts, as shown by Green-Pedersen [1984,<br />

chapter E].<br />

But what are intrinsic and extrinsic middles? An extrinsic middle is a proposition<br />

not containing <strong>the</strong> terms that form <strong>the</strong> antecedent and <strong>the</strong> consequent <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong><br />

putative consequence, but which is a general rule describing <strong>the</strong> fact (ontological,<br />

logical or o<strong>the</strong>r) that warrants <strong>the</strong> passage from <strong>the</strong> antecedent to <strong>the</strong> consequent.<br />

An intrinsic middle, by contrast, is formed by <strong>the</strong> very terms that form <strong>the</strong> antecedent<br />

and <strong>the</strong> consequent <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> putative consequence. Ockham says that some<br />

formal consequences hold only in virtue <strong>of</strong> an extrinsic middle, while o<strong>the</strong>rs need<br />

an intrinsic as well as an extrinsic middle to hold. Syllogisms, for example, hold<br />

only in virtue <strong>of</strong> extrinsic middles; a consequence such as ‘Only a man is a donkey,<br />

<strong>the</strong>refore every donkey is a man’ holds in virtue <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> following extrinsic middle:<br />

‘an exclusive and a universal with transposed terms signify <strong>the</strong> same and are<br />

convertible’. But a consequence such as ‘Socrates is not running, <strong>the</strong>refore a man<br />

is not running’ requires that <strong>the</strong> intrinsic middle ‘Socrates is a man’ be true in<br />

order to hold (and it still requires an extrinsic middle to validate it mediately).<br />

(Ockham, Summa <strong>Logic</strong>ae, p. 588).<br />

What exactly a material consequence is for Ockham is still a matter <strong>of</strong> controversy<br />

among scholars, as <strong>the</strong> passage where this notion is explained is known to<br />

be corrupted (Summa <strong>Logic</strong>ae, p. 589). 45 Ockham gives two examples <strong>of</strong> material<br />

consequences, one <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> ex impossibili kind (from an impossible proposition anything<br />

follows) and one <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> ad necessarium kind (a necessary proposition follows<br />

45 See [Schupp, 1993] on <strong>the</strong> corruption <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> text.

Hooray! Your file is uploaded and ready to be published.

Saved successfully!

Ooh no, something went wrong!