22.06.2013 Views

Handbook of the History of Logic: - Fordham University Faculty

Handbook of the History of Logic: - Fordham University Faculty

Handbook of the History of Logic: - Fordham University Faculty

SHOW MORE
SHOW LESS

You also want an ePaper? Increase the reach of your titles

YUMPU automatically turns print PDFs into web optimized ePapers that Google loves.

The Assimilation <strong>of</strong> Aristotelian and Arabic <strong>Logic</strong> up to <strong>the</strong> Later Thirteenth Century 313<br />

4.5 The Sophistici Elenchi<br />

The Latin version <strong>of</strong> Sophistici elenchi by Boethius began to circulate in <strong>the</strong><br />

1120s. 74 It was retranslated from <strong>the</strong> Greek a little later by James <strong>of</strong> Venice<br />

and later in <strong>the</strong> thirteenth century a third Latin translation appeared in 1269 by<br />

William <strong>of</strong> Moerbeke. It relatively quickly became a central part <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> new logic<br />

developing in <strong>the</strong> late twelfth century. As with <strong>the</strong> o<strong>the</strong>r logic works <strong>of</strong> Aristotle<br />

<strong>the</strong> earliest commentaries were literal commentaries, that is, <strong>the</strong>y proceed by first<br />

quoting <strong>the</strong> text from Aristotle and <strong>the</strong>n expanding on it before turning to <strong>the</strong><br />

next bit <strong>of</strong> text. Towards <strong>the</strong> end <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> thirteenth century so-called question commentaries<br />

started to appear. These were more problametising by asking specific<br />

problematic questions based on Aristotle’s text.<br />

Although <strong>the</strong> Sophistici Elenchi belongs to <strong>the</strong> logica nova parts <strong>of</strong> it was well<br />

known before <strong>the</strong> 1120’s. The reason for this is a line in Chapter 6 <strong>of</strong> De interpretatione.<br />

In his discussion <strong>of</strong> contradictions, Aristotle notes that <strong>the</strong> subject<br />

and <strong>the</strong> predicate <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> contradictory propositions must be identical, and <strong>the</strong>n he<br />

adds that “<strong>the</strong> identity <strong>of</strong> subject and predicate <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> contradictory propositions<br />

must not be ‘equivocal’. Indeed <strong>the</strong>re are definite qualifiers besides this, which we<br />

make to meet <strong>the</strong> cauistries <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> sophists” (17a35-7). This note makes Boethius<br />

outline parts <strong>of</strong> Aristotle’s doctrine in <strong>the</strong> Sophistici Elenchi in his second, more<br />

detailed, commentary on <strong>the</strong> De interpretatione. Boethius mentions six cases in<br />

which <strong>the</strong> contradictions <strong>of</strong> propositions are frustrated by fallacies, namely in <strong>the</strong><br />

fallacies <strong>of</strong> (i) equivocation, (ii) univocation, (iii) diverse parts, (iv) relatives, (v)<br />

diverse times, and (vi) diverse modes.<br />

The fact that this discussion is included in a commentary on De interpretatione<br />

is historically very important. De interpretatione is about terms in propositions<br />

and <strong>the</strong> discussion <strong>of</strong> fallacies forces twelfth century logicians to think about ways<br />

in which terms can be taken in a proposition. Very early in <strong>the</strong> twelfth century<br />

one can <strong>the</strong>refore find formulations like <strong>the</strong> following in commentaries on De interpretatione,<br />

namely that “<strong>the</strong> interpretation <strong>of</strong> a term is determine by its use in<br />

a proposition.” 75 This is <strong>the</strong> fundamental idea behind supposition <strong>the</strong>ory and <strong>the</strong><br />

logica modernorum.<br />

The discussion <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> fallacies did not single handily generate <strong>the</strong> doctrine <strong>of</strong><br />

supposition, since, as de Rijk shows 76 , <strong>the</strong> development <strong>of</strong> grammar in <strong>the</strong> twelfth<br />

century was also essential to this development. It is clear though that early commentaries<br />

on <strong>the</strong> Sophistici Elenchi in <strong>the</strong> later twelfth century played a very<br />

important part in formulating supposition <strong>the</strong>ory. I will not go in to this fur<strong>the</strong>r<br />

since this falls outside <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> scope <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> present chapter.<br />

It is towards <strong>the</strong> latter half <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> twelfth century that one can find <strong>the</strong> first<br />

Latin commentaries on <strong>the</strong> Sophistici Elenchi that are based on Aristotle’s original<br />

text. It is also <strong>the</strong>n that <strong>the</strong> discussion <strong>of</strong> fallacies are formed and divided in <strong>the</strong><br />

74 See Aristotle, De sophisticis elenchis, xi-xv.<br />

75 See [de Rijk, 1962, 48].<br />

76 See [de Rijk, 1967, I, 95–125].

Hooray! Your file is uploaded and ready to be published.

Saved successfully!

Ooh no, something went wrong!