22.06.2013 Views

Handbook of the History of Logic: - Fordham University Faculty

Handbook of the History of Logic: - Fordham University Faculty

Handbook of the History of Logic: - Fordham University Faculty

SHOW MORE
SHOW LESS

Create successful ePaper yourself

Turn your PDF publications into a flip-book with our unique Google optimized e-Paper software.

Port Royal: The Stirrings <strong>of</strong> Modernity 693<br />

can be seen as a premiss. Given <strong>the</strong> account <strong>of</strong> logic advocated in this work,<br />

especially <strong>the</strong> second discourse where logic was seen as giving rules for all actions<br />

<strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> mind, it is no surprise that this concern is included in logic. But it is also<br />

<strong>the</strong> case that dilemma arguments which have faulty premisses can mask that fact<br />

by having <strong>the</strong> same form as sound arguments. It is important to remember that<br />

Arnauld and Nicole see <strong>the</strong> whole purpose <strong>of</strong> an argument as a process <strong>of</strong> showing<br />

<strong>the</strong> truth <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> conclusion, and so in some sense starting with <strong>the</strong> conclusion as<br />

a problem. Right reasoning involves a clear progression from clearer premises to<br />

<strong>the</strong> problematic conclusion. In <strong>the</strong> case <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> fallacious dilemmas and <strong>the</strong> o<strong>the</strong>r<br />

fallacies discussed in chapters 19 and 20 <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> third part, <strong>the</strong>re is a pattern <strong>of</strong><br />

reasoning that gives <strong>the</strong> picture <strong>of</strong> a correct argument, but does not succeed.<br />

The section on fallacies reviews <strong>the</strong> standard fallacies mostly taken from Aristotle’s<br />

Sophistical Refutations: <strong>the</strong> ignoratio elenchi or proving something o<strong>the</strong>r<br />

than what was in question; petition de principe, or supposing for true what is in<br />

question; non causa pro causa or taking for a cause what isn’t a cause; imperfect<br />

enumeration, which here is not so much a hasty generalization, but a failure to consider<br />

options; <strong>the</strong> fallacy <strong>of</strong> accident; composition and division; <strong>the</strong> fallacy <strong>of</strong> taking<br />

something affirmed conditionally to something affirmed unconditionally; and fallacies<br />

<strong>of</strong> ambiguity. A brief remark is <strong>the</strong>n made about incomplete or defective<br />

inductions, postponing that discussion to <strong>the</strong> section on method. The discussion<br />

<strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong>se fallacies is clear and quite lively, but not especially innovative. 27 In many<br />

<strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong>ir examples, Arnauld and Nicole use <strong>the</strong> discussion to accuse Aristotle <strong>of</strong><br />

committing several <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> fallacies he himself talks about.<br />

The discussion <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong>se traditional fallacies is supplemented by a section on<br />

fallacies committed in ordinary life and discourse. These are divided into sophisms<br />

<strong>of</strong> self-love, and sophism arising from <strong>the</strong> objects <strong>the</strong>mselves. The section on<br />

sophisms <strong>of</strong> self-love, which contains some <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> more entertaining examples in <strong>the</strong><br />

<strong>Logic</strong>, focuses on reasons o<strong>the</strong>r than <strong>the</strong> truth for which one may hold something.<br />

The opening remarks <strong>of</strong> this section is similar to much later discussions <strong>of</strong> what is<br />

sometimes called <strong>the</strong> fallacy <strong>of</strong> subjectivism. 28 Arnauld and Nicole have in mind<br />

such arguments as <strong>the</strong> following:<br />

I am from such and such a country, <strong>the</strong>refore I ought to believe that a<br />

certain saint preached <strong>the</strong> Gospel <strong>the</strong>re. (262)<br />

I love him, <strong>the</strong>refore he is <strong>the</strong> most able man in <strong>the</strong> world: I hate him,<br />

<strong>the</strong>refore he is worthless. (263)<br />

27 For a fur<strong>the</strong>r discussion <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong>se fallacies, see [Woods, 2000, 36–38]. Woods calls this first<br />

group “scientific sophisms” because <strong>of</strong> a remark Arnauld and Nicole make at <strong>the</strong> beginning <strong>of</strong><br />

<strong>the</strong> next chapter contrasting sophisms <strong>of</strong> ordinary life and discourse to those involving matters<br />

<strong>of</strong> science (260).<br />

28 See for example, <strong>the</strong> discussion in Kelley, The Art <strong>of</strong> Reasoning, which treats subjectivism as<br />

a fallacy [Kelley, 1998, 126–127]. Kelley’s analysis <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> pattern <strong>of</strong> reasoning as I believe/want p<br />

to be true <strong>the</strong>refore p is true. Compare this with <strong>the</strong> passage in <strong>the</strong> <strong>Logic</strong> (263), where discussing<br />

<strong>the</strong> “sophisms and illusions <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> heart”, Arnauld and Nicole say <strong>the</strong>se consist in transporting<br />

our passions to <strong>the</strong> objects <strong>of</strong> our passions and judging <strong>the</strong>m as we want or desire <strong>the</strong>m to be.

Hooray! Your file is uploaded and ready to be published.

Saved successfully!

Ooh no, something went wrong!