22.06.2013 Views

Handbook of the History of Logic: - Fordham University Faculty

Handbook of the History of Logic: - Fordham University Faculty

Handbook of the History of Logic: - Fordham University Faculty

SHOW MORE
SHOW LESS

Create successful ePaper yourself

Turn your PDF publications into a flip-book with our unique Google optimized e-Paper software.

148 Ian Wilks<br />

This indeed is <strong>the</strong> approach <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> Melidunenses, Montani, and Parvipontani<br />

alike, although <strong>the</strong>y differ in how this approach is carried through. The<br />

Melidunenses adapt Abelard’s view more directly, taking <strong>the</strong> argument to consist<br />

<strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> enuntiabilia corresponding to <strong>the</strong> premises used in establishing <strong>the</strong> conclusion;<br />

<strong>the</strong> arbitrariness <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> sounds or letter shapes constituting <strong>the</strong> spoken or<br />

written expressions <strong>of</strong> those enuntiabilia <strong>the</strong>refore in no sense imparts arbitrariness<br />

to <strong>the</strong> argument as a whole. The Montani and Parvipontani have a more<br />

complex account. They view <strong>the</strong> relation <strong>of</strong> premises to conclusion as implicational<br />

ra<strong>the</strong>r than inferential, so that “A <strong>the</strong>refore B” is construed as being at<br />

heart <strong>the</strong> conditional “If A <strong>the</strong>n B.” For both <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong>se groups <strong>the</strong> argument is<br />

<strong>the</strong> enuntiabile expressed by such a conditional. Given an inference like “Socrates<br />

is a man; <strong>the</strong>refore Socrates is an animal,” <strong>the</strong> Parvipontani take <strong>the</strong> argument<br />

as being <strong>the</strong> enuntiabile corresponding to this conditional: “If Socrates is a man<br />

he is an animal.” The Montani adopt much <strong>the</strong> same approach, except that <strong>the</strong><br />

conditional takes a more general form: “If something is a man it is an animal.”<br />

The enuntiabile corresponding to this conditional form is thus identified as <strong>the</strong> argument<br />

<strong>of</strong> “Socrates is a man; <strong>the</strong>refore Socrates is a mortal,” <strong>of</strong> “Plato is a man;<br />

<strong>the</strong>refore Plato is a mortal,” and <strong>of</strong> all o<strong>the</strong>r possible substitution instances <strong>of</strong> this<br />

form. Finally, <strong>the</strong> response <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> Porretani lies a little apart from <strong>the</strong>se o<strong>the</strong>rs in<br />

appealing not to an enuntiabile at all but to a relation <strong>of</strong> terms, in particular <strong>the</strong><br />

relation <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> middle term to <strong>the</strong> o<strong>the</strong>rs. The argument is simply this relation.<br />

Since <strong>the</strong> relation is assuredly an objective one, it thus avoids what appears to be<br />

<strong>the</strong> problem with holding that an argument is nothing but <strong>the</strong> meaningful words<br />

<strong>of</strong> which it is composed [Iwakuma, 2004, pp. 318–320].<br />

There is controversy not only about <strong>the</strong> nature <strong>of</strong> an argument but about <strong>the</strong><br />

very relationship between syllogisms and topical inferences. Recall that Abelard<br />

distinguishes between complete and incomplete entailment, ascribing to syllogisms<br />

<strong>the</strong> status <strong>of</strong> being complete by virtue <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong>ir syntactic form. The strength <strong>of</strong><br />

topical inferences is understood, as we have seen, in a very different way [Stump,<br />

1989, pp. 96–97]. This is a unique view at <strong>the</strong> time Abelard initially propounds<br />

it [Green-Pederson, 1987, p. 198]. His predecessors typically view syllogisms as<br />

deriving <strong>the</strong>ir strength in <strong>the</strong> same way all topical inferences do, and topics are<br />

assigned to <strong>the</strong>m, just as to o<strong>the</strong>r inferences. The topics for syllogisms simply tend<br />

to be descriptions <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> relevant syllogistic mood, descriptions set in <strong>the</strong> form <strong>of</strong><br />

topical rules. Abelard’s insistence that <strong>the</strong>re is something fundamentally distinct<br />

about <strong>the</strong> syllogism that sets it apart from o<strong>the</strong>r inferences is <strong>the</strong>refore a novel<br />

view, and is regarded in his own time as a characteristic view, both <strong>of</strong> himself and<br />

<strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> Nominales. The view that syllogisms are at heart inferences, best expressed<br />

as conditionals with <strong>the</strong> conclusion as consequent, naturally encourages <strong>the</strong> notion<br />

that <strong>the</strong>y, like o<strong>the</strong>r conditionals, require topical warrant; but <strong>the</strong> implicative (as<br />

opposed to inferential) approach to <strong>the</strong> syllogism taken by o<strong>the</strong>r schools <strong>the</strong>refore<br />

encourages some level <strong>of</strong> dissent from Abelard’s view. The Montani and Porretani<br />

both maintain that <strong>the</strong> inferential linkage at work in syllogisms is ultimately a<br />

matter <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> topical relations that exist between <strong>the</strong>ir terms; logical form <strong>the</strong>n

Hooray! Your file is uploaded and ready to be published.

Saved successfully!

Ooh no, something went wrong!